What[u1]  is the Human Being?:

Kant’s Theory of Human Nature

 

Chapter 3:

Kant’s Empirical Anthropology

 

We must . . . concede that through inner sense we intuit ourselves only as we are internally affected by our selves, i.e., as far as inner intuition is concerned we cognize our own subject only as appearance but not in accordance with what it is in itself.  (B156)

Xxx add a couple other good quotes (one from empirical psychology lectures, one from anthropology, be sure to cover nonintrospective knowing xxx.

“voluntary action (which belongs among natural causes as well)” (20:196, KU first tinro)

 

 

            In the last chapter, we saw Kant’s “transcendental” account of the human being, his examination of the cognitive, volitional, and affective dimensions of the human being from the standpoint of the a priori, normative, autonomously given laws that govern those faculties. But Kant also engaged intensely in empirical debates about human beings. The next three chapters focus on different dimensions of Kant's empirical account of human beings. First, in this chapter, I examine Kant's overall empirical psychology: his accounts of the different faculties of human beings, the causal laws that describe the activity of those faculties, and the natural bases of such powers in “natural predispositions” and “germs” found in humans’ biological nature.[1] In chapter five, I turn to two more specific aspects of Kant's empirical anthropology, his treatments of human evil and of the historical nature of the human species. And in chapter six, I turn to Kant's accounts of human difference.

            All these elements of Kant’s empirical account of human beings depend upon the legitimacy of deriving general claims about human nature from observations – both introspective and external – of human beings. Kant discusses the challenges facing any such empirical study in detail, and Kant is so attentive to these challenges that he has often been taken to reject the possibility of empirical human sciences altogether. In that context, I begin this chapter with a defense of the possibility of a Kantian empirical science and an examination of precisely what Kant's account of human science is. In the context of a better understanding of the nature and limits of any human science, we can then move on to the details of Kant’s empirical anthropology.

 

1. Can there be an empirical science of human beings?

            Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason would seem to pave the way, fairly straightforwardly, for the empirical study of human beings. Although Kant insists throughout the Critique that “xxx we can have no knowledge of ourselves as we are in ourselves” (xxx), he always adds “but only as we appear to ourselves xxx” (xxx). For Kant, the human being, like everything else in nature, has an appearance; there is what he refers to elsewhere as a “homo phenomenon” (MM 6:418), referring to his famous distinction between “phenomena” – objects as they appear to us in the world of experience – and “noumena” – things as they are in themselves independent of the possibility of experiencing them. And when Kant lays out the principles that human beings can know a priori about objects of experience, he defends these principles as transcendental conditions of the possibility of objects in time­ -- the form of inner sense that governs both inner psychological “objects” and external, physical objects – precisely in order to ensure that all experience – inner as well as outer – will be governed by these principles[KP2] . Moreover, even in precisely the parts of the Critique of Pure Reason where Kant most emphasizes the possibility of a human freedom that is beyond the possibility of empirical study, he also insists that human beings insofar as they appear in the world are subject to such study: “all the actions of a human being are determined in accord with the order of nature,” and “if we could investigate all the appearances . . . there would be no human action we could not predict with certainty”(A549/B577).[2]  He gives a striking example to illustrate this general point.

Let us take a voluntary action, for example, a malicious lie . . . .  First of all, we endeavor to discover the motives to which it has been due, and then, secondly, we proceed to determine how far the action . . . can be imputed to the offender.  As regards the first question, we trace the empirical character of the action to its sources, finding these in defective education, bad company, in part also in the viciousness of a natural disposition insensitive to shame . . . .  We proceed in this enquiry just as we should in ascertaining for a given natural effect the series of its determining causes.  But although we believe the action is thus determined, we nonetheless blame the agent[j3] .  XXX ADD MORE OF THIS QUOTE TO MAKE CLEAR THAT THIS IMPLIES FREEDOM XXX (A554-55/B 582-83, emphasis added; cf. too 29:1019-20)

In the Grounding, Kant reiterates this: “everything which takes place [is] determined without exception in accordance with laws of nature” (4:455).[3] And in the Critique of Practical Reason, he insists that if we knew the relevant preconditions, “we could calculate a human being’s conduct for the future with as much certainty as a lunar or solar eclipse” (5: 99)[j4] 

            Despite this apparent insistence on and even apparent transcendental grounding for the empirical study of human beings, there are four main reasons to call into question whether Kant can allow for any kind of scientific study of human beings at all. First and most basically, Kant claims in the Critique of Pure Reason that “experience . . . gives us no true universality” (A1-2), which seems to preclude the possibility of any empirical human science applying to human beings in general[4] One might be able to have descriptions of various humans in various contexts, but no real human science of the sort proposed by philosophers ranging from Locke and Hume to Wolff and Tetens, nor a real psychology of the sort practice by human scientists today. Second, Kant seems to explicitly reject the possibility of any empirical human science in his Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science (xxx), [KP5] the book in which Kant extended the a priori principles of the first Critique into the foundations of physics. There, in the context of discussing what sorts of study can be made into a proper science, Kant explicitly says, “The empirical doctrine of the soul [psychology] can . . . never become . . . a science of the soul, nor even a psychological experimental doctrine” (4:471[u6] ). Third, an empirical – and especially a causal – account of human action might seem to conflict with Kant’s claims about human freedom (discussed in the last chapter).[5] Finally, Kant often mentions specific challenges with the study of human beings (especially in introspection), both epistemic concerns such as the fact that “if a human being notices that someone is . . . trying to study him, he . . . either . . . cannot show himself as he really is or . . . does not want to be known as he is” (7:121) and moral dangers such as that “self-observation . . . is the most direct path to illuminism or even terrorism” (7:133). These comments might seem to suggest that even if empirical human science is possible in principle, it is both unreliable and dangerous in practice.[6] In the rest of this section, I take up each of these issues in turn. The result by the end of this section will be a clearer sense of the challenges facing the empirical study of human beings and thereby a clearer sense of Kant’s approach to such study.

 

            With respect to the problem of universality, the concern is both easy to state and easy to alleviate. Kant’s accounts of human nature purport to be universal. He says that anthropology must begin with “universal knowledge” and that the subject of anthropology is human beings as such. His accounts of mental powers, the laws that govern them, and the predisposition that underlie these are all intended to refer to human beings as such. Of course, Kant includes some empirical claims that are not universal, such as his descriptions of women and various races (see chapter six). But the vast majority of Kant’s empirical human science is universal. The apparent problem arises because of Kant’s general account of knowledge, in which Kant connects universality with necessity and argues that the only possible basis for universal claims is a priori reasoning. In the Critique of Pure Reason, he says, “Experience tells us, indeed, what is, but not that it must necessarily be so, and not otherwise. It therefore gives us no true universality” (A1-2, cf. B3-4, A91/B124, A196/B241). Whereas in his empirical studies of human beings, Kant seems to want to extend his claims to all people without exception, his general claims about universality would make this extension seem “merely fictitious” (A196/B241). One seems forced to choose between anthropology being universal and its being empirical, when Kant clearly states that it is both.

            In fact, however, Kant’s claims about the connection between universality and a priori reasoning are limited to what he calls “strict universality.” [KP7] In the first Critique, Kant repeatedly mentions a kind of universality that experience can provide, an “assumed and comparative universality” (B3): “empirical rules . . . can acquire through induction . . . comparative universality, that is, extensive applicability” (B124/A91). According to this kind of universality,

We can properly only say, therefore, that, so far as we have hitherto observed, there is no exception to this or that rule . . . Empirical universality is . . . an arbitrary extension of a validity holding in most cases to one which holds in all, for instance, in the proposition “all bodies are heavy.” (B 3-4[u8] )

Given its focus on a priori conditions of experience, it is unsurprising that first Critique downplays the role of this kind of empirical universal judgment. But Kant’s insistence that this universality is merely “extensive applicability” is only a contrast to that strict universality according to which “no exception is allowed as possible” (B4, my emphasis). As his example of heavy bodies makes clear, such judgments need not be taken as merely claims that something is widespread. They hold without exception, but with the possibility of exception.[7][KP9] 

            Kant’s response to the concern about universality has three important implications for the nature of his empirical study of human beings. First, Kant’s account of comparative universality shows how empirical human sciences, even when they purport to describe human beings as such, can be compatible with Kant’s account of knowledge. Second, this way of saving empirical human science shows that such study must always be taken to provide an account of how human beings in fact are, but not how they must be. This contingency in human nature is what Russell rightly saw but mistakenly took to have implications for transcendental philosophy. And, as we will see in the next chapter, Kant makes use (rightly) of this contingency in human nature to explain the nature of human evil. Finally, the fact that empirical human sciences are always only comparatively universal requires and allows a healthy degree of humility about the status of any particular claims within anthropology. Kant provides detailed empirical arguments in order to go beyond mere claims about widespread human phenomena toward generalizations that apply to all human beings. But because these generalizations provide only comparative universality, Kant (and Kantian anthropology) need not take any particular claims to be infallible. More data might require revision of such claims, though Kant thinks that he has good (but not indefeasible) reasons for thinking that no such data will arise.

 

            The second concern about the possibility of a Kantian empirical anthropology arises from a claim in Kant's Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science:

The empirical doctrine of the soul [i.e., human mind] must always remain even further removed than chemistry from the rank of what may be called a natural science proper . . . It can . . . never become anything more than a historical (and as such, as much as possible) systematic natural doctrine of the internal sense, i.e., a natural description of the soul, but not a science of the soul, nor even a psychological experimental doctrine.  This is the reason why . . . the general name of natural science . . . belongs to the doctrine of body alone.  (4:471, see too 20:238[8], 28:679)

Many[9] have taken this passage to imply that Kant opposes any kind of serious empirical study of the causal principles underlying mental life. But Kant’s argument against psychology as a science employs very specific objections and Kant allows that psychology can be a “historical systematic natural doctrine of the inner sense” (4:471) and even a “natural science . . . improperly so called, . . . [which] would treat its object . . . according to laws of experience” (4:468). What Kant objects to is applying to psychology a very particular conception of science, as a study “whose certainty is apodictic,” which must thus consist in “a priori principles” (4:468) and in particular in the application of “mathematics” to its subject matter (4:470).[10] Elsewhere, in fact, Kant even insists,

The sphere of human beings . . . deserves to be presented together as a whole, and not alongside of other sciences. For physics is knowledge of the object of outer sense, and the knowledge of human beings as the object of inner sense, constitutes just such a sphere. Consequently, it deserves just such effort, and to be treated as such a science in academia, as is physics. (25:472-3)[11]

Kant does not here mean that empirical anthropology will be a science in the same sense as physics, since it will not have a mathematical, a priori foundation. But anthropology can still bring the phenomena of inner sense under empirically-determined rules, albeit only comparatively universal ones.

            The third concern about the possibility of Kantian empirical science arises from Kant’s account of human freedom. As we saw in the last chapter, Kant’s account of freedom involves a commitment to what Henry Allison has called an “Incorporation Thesis,” according to which human beings act only on motives that they “incorporate” into maxims. Many commentators have rightly pointed out that this account of free human action offers a different conception of moral psychology than the traditional empiricist belief-desire model according to which human beings are simply motivated by the strongest active desire.[12] But this insightful alternative approach to thinking about human action can seem to conflict with Kant’s empirical account of human action. In particular, Kant argues that human actions are susceptible to causal and even historical influences and offers a model of human action that is remarkably similar to the empiricist belief-desire model. Many Kantians attracted by the role of freedom and the related incorporation thesis are resistant to the idea that there might be a Kantian psychology that empirically explains human behavior. As one such commentator puts it, “if the moral law determines choice by exerting a force that is stronger than the alternatives, moral conduct will result from the balance of whatever psychological forces are acting on the will . . . It is not clear that this model leaves room for any real notion of will or choice” (Reath 1989: 290-91).[13]

            Given Kant’s transcendental idealism, however, an empirical and even causal model of human behavior does leave room for real choice, though not within the empirical psychology itself. Kant’s account of agency in terms of the Incorporation Thesis is an account of transcendental freedom, an account that, for Kant at least, is consistent with the familiar empiricist picture of agency[KP10] .[14] [15][u11]  As we saw in the last chapter, Kant's transcendental anthropology of cognition shows that human beings experience everything – including themselves – in terms of a structure of cognition that interprets change in terms of causal relationships. But this metaphysics of the empirical world leaves room for a different standpoint from which freedom is possible, and Kant's transcendental anthropology of desire – his moral philosophy – makes clear that human agents must see themselves as free causes of their actions. Thus while human scientists can and must investigate human actions as natural events that occur in accordance with empirically discernible causal powers, human agents can and must deliberate and evaluate[16] actions as the results of free choices. And, conversely, while there is nothing wrong with focusing on agency from the standpoint of freedom (as so many Kantians do), the possibility of describing human actions from the perspective of freedom does not preclude the possibility of giving causal accounts of such actions within the context of an empirical human science. This implies, of course, that Kant’s empirical anthropology is only empirical; it does not provide access to the nature of the human being as it is in itself, what Kant calls the “homo noumenon” (MM 6:418, cf. 7:397-400). Kant does believe that it is possible to have access to what the human being is like in itself (as we saw in the last chapter), but empirical anthropology provides no such access.

 

            The fourth and final problem for the possibility of a rigorous empirical investigation of human beings lies in specific problems that arise when trying to observe and study humans. In his Anthropology, Kant says about his proposed science of human beings,

     [A]ll such attempts to arrive at such a science with thoroughness encounter considerable difficulties that are inherent in human nature itself.  

1. If a human being notices that someone is observing him and trying to study him, he will either appear embarrassed (self-conscious) and cannot show himself as he really is; or he dissembles, and does not want to be known as he is.

     2. Even if he only wants to study himself, he will reach a critical point, particularly as concerns his condition in affect, which normally does not allow dissimulation: that is to say, when the incentives are active, he does not observe himself, and when he does observe himself, the incentives are at rest.

     3. Circumstances of place and time, when they are constant, produce habits which, as is said, are second nature, and make it difficult for the human being to judge how to consider himself, but even more difficult to judge how he should form an idea of others with whom he is in contact; for the variation of conditions in which the human being is placed by his fate or, if he is an adventurer, places himself, make it very difficult for anthropology to rise to the rank of a formal science. (7:120-1)

And in a draft of his anthropology, Kant adds,

[T]he I which has been observed by itself is a sum total of so many objects of inner perception that psychology has plenty to do in tracing everything that lies hidden in it. And psychology may not ever hope to complete this task and answer satisfactorily the question: “What is the human being?” (7:398-99)

For Kant, empirical study of human beings proceeds by means of both introspection and observation of others, and both of these forms of study face several of the problems Kant describes here: mental life is just intrinsically complex, human beings typically act differently when being observed,[17] self-observation is inhibited by the fact that many of the most interesting and important activities in human life preclude the calm and attentive work of introspection,[18] and human beings can develop contingent characteristics – habits of time and place – that seem essential. The result of all of this can be a desperation about the possibility of ever (empirically) answering the question, “What is the human being?”[19]

            Despite these cautions, Kant claims that “an anthropology . . . that is systematically designed” is possible and “yields an advantage for the reading public,” including the promotion of “the growth of [this] science for the common good” (7:121-2). Kant even holds that such an anthropology begins with a “knowledge of human beings” that is “general” (7:120) and even that “anthropology . . . is provided with a content by inner sense” (7: xxxfrom draft anthro, cf. 25:252, 863-5). And while Kant warns about the dangers of such introspection, he also insists that it can be done in a way that is relatively free from such dangers. Self-observation becomes dangerous when “we make supposed discoveries of what we ourselves have carried into ourselves” (7:133), acting as thought the apparently involuntary flow of our thoughts is due to some sort of supernatural inspiration. But Kant insists that observing oneself is also a duty (6:441-2), and he gives both general advice and specific examples of how to introspect well. Moreover, Kant insists that this introspection provides a basis for further study, in that one can make use of the general knowledge gained through introspection to interpret others. Kant explains,

If we want to judge about other people, we must alter our point of view, namely

     1. transpose my point of view and then

     2. put myself in the other’s point of view . . . To take a point of view is a skill which one can acquire by practice. (25:475)

Moreover, Kant suggests that reading the right kind of literature – he suggests Shakespeare and Montaigne, for example[20][KP12] [u13]  – can help cultivate proper self-observation and supplement the limits of self-study in the acquisition of general knowledge of human beings. Given that general knowledge, travel and the reading of travel literature provides further material for reflection on both human nature in general and “local knowledge” of the varieties of human beings.[21] Disciplined self-study, supplemented by careful study of others and reading literature by those skilled in putting themselves into others’ points of view, can alleviate the problems faced by any attempt “to observe human beings and their conduct, [and] to bring their pheno­mena under rules, [which] is the purpose of anthropology” (25:472). While Kant doubts the possibility of a wholly satisfactory empirical psychology, his anthropology aims to develop as full an empirical account as possible, or at least an empirical account of human beings “from which a prudent use in life can . . . be drawn” (25:472, cf. 7: 119, xxx).

 

            In this section, we have seen four central objections to the possibility of an empirical science of human beings within Kant’s philosophy. From Kant’s responses to these objections, we have made clear what form such a Kantian empirical anthropology must take. It will be only a science “improperly so called” in that it will provide only comparatively universal claims about what human beings in fact are in general, rather than what human nature is of necessity. And this “science” will not be particularly mathematical, but rather will classify the phenomena of human life into a “systematic natural doctrine of the internal sense,” that is, a structured account of the different sorts of mental states operative in human life that brings these phenomena under general rules. The account will also be empirical both in its method and in its subject matter. Empirical anthropology does not aim to give an account of the thoughts and motives of humans qua free agents, but only an account of the thoughts and motives that appear in our experience of human beings. Thus this anthropology is a “third-person” psychology rather than a “first-person” account of how to think or choose (see especially 7: xxx from draft xxx for clarification of this point). Finally, empirical anthropology is difficult and fallible. Kant refers to the introspection required as a “hard descent into the Hell of self-knowledge” (25:7, check quote and translation xxx) and insists that both self-observation itself and the extension of introspection to claims about human nature require “skill.” One must work through the challenges of dissimulation and deceit, in oneself as well as others, and the difficult task of distinguishing mere habitual norms from true aspects of human nature as such. And one must carefully observe ones own tendencies without succumbing to the dangers of either fanatical obsession with one’s passing mental states nor self-deception about one’s motives. Because one can never be completely sure that one has avoided these problems, one’s empirical anthropology remains ever open to revision in the light of new data or better understandings of old data. In the end, though, Kant thinks that it is possible to get a “science” of human nature that is empirical, systematic, and universal, even if also incomplete and fallible.

 

            Given that a science of human beings is possible, we can now turn to the content of such a science. The rest of this chapter will look at three key elements of Kant's empirical anthropology. First, I explain the role of “faculties” and “powers” in Kant's account of the human being, and in this context I show how Kant extends the work of Mendellsohn, Tetens, and Crusius, who all argued against Wolff’s attempt to reduce the powers of the human soul to a single one. Second, I discuss the relationships between these powers and how Kant moves from his account of powers to accounts of the causal laws in accordance with which human mental life operates. Finally, I turn to the biological bases of these powers in “natural predispositions” and “germs” in human nature, explaining in this context Kant's innovative work in the philosophy of biology insofar as this bears on his account of the human organism.

 

2. Kant’s Faculty Psychology

            In chapter two, we saw how Wolff’s attempt to reduce the variety of different causal powers in the human mind (or “soul”) to a single faculty of representation was resisted both by his “followers,” such as Baumgarten, Mendelssohn and Tetens, and by opponents such as Crusius. Both Mendelssohn and Tetens, in different ways, developed tripartite conceptions of the human mind, and Tetens, in particular, began the process of systematically working out a wide variety of different mental powers. Kant continued this tradition of reaction against Wolff with a detailed and systematic account of the structure of the human mind. Kant defends his own tripartite distinction of the human mind into faculties of cognition, feeling, and desire, on the grounds that

We [can] have pleasure or displeasure without desiring or abhorring . . . Pleasure or displeasure is thus something entirely different from the faculty of desire. . . There are also many representations which are connected with neither pleasure nor displeasure, and thus the cognitive faculty is wholly distinct from the feeling of pleasure or displeasure. (29:877-8)[22]

Each of the three basic faculties includes several distinct basic powers, none of which is reducible to others. Within the faculty of cognition, for instance, Kant includes distinct basic powers such as the five senses, imagination, understanding, and reason, each of which is governed by its own laws. These powers can be organized, however, in terms of a distinction between “higher” and “lower” powers that cuts across the tripartite division of faculties.

Kant adopts the distinction between “higher” and “lower” faculties of cognition, feeling, and desire from Baumgarten, but whereas Baumgarten sought to reduce all of these to a single faculty of representation, Kant (like Crusius[23]) insists that they are irreducible. For Kant, “lower” faculties are primarily receptive, while “higher” faculties are “self-active” or “spontaneous” (28:228, 29:880, 28:584), by which Kant does not mean the transcendental freedom of the homo noumenon but a “comparative concept of freedom” according to which “actions are caused from within, by representations produced by our own powers, whereby desires are evoked on occasion of circumstances and hence actions are produced at our own discretion” (5:96).[24] Thus we can broadly outline six different “faculties” in Kant’s empirical psychology: higher and lower cognition, higher and lower feeling, and higher and lower desire.

With respect to cognition, the lower faculty is referred to broadly as “sensibility” (Sinnlichkeit) and includes the senses (Sinne) and the imagination, each of which is further subdivided (Cf. 7:140-1, 153ff.; 25:29f., 269f.; 28:59f., 230f., 585, 672f., 869f., 737f.; and 29: 882f). The senses include the five outer senses as well as inner sense, and the imagination includes memory, anticipation of future events, and the “productive” or “fictive” imagination. The higher faculty of cognition is often referred to by the general term “understanding” (Verstand) and includes three specific cognitive powers: reason, the understanding (Verstand) in a narrow sense, and the power of judgment.[25] Moreover, just as “there is a higher and a lower cognitive faculty[,] so there is also a rational and a sensible feeling of pleasure or displeasure (and so it is also with the faculty of desire)” (29:877).[26]  As with the cognitive faculty, the distinction between the higher and lower faculties of desire is based on the distinction between the senses and the understanding: “all desires are . . . [either] intellectual or sensitive” (29:894).  But in the case of desire, what is relevant is not the nature of the desire itself but the cognitive state that produces the desire.[27]  “The representations which produce determinations [of desire] are either sensible or intellectual” (28: 674-5).  Insofar as a desire is the direct result of the senses or unmediated imagination, is it part of the “lower” faculty of desire.  Insofar as it proceeds from the understanding or reason, a desire falls under the “higher” faculty of desire.

            We can summarize Kant’s taxonomy of faculties of the soul as follows:

 

The faculties (and powers) of the soul

 

Cognition (representations)

Feeling (satisfaction and dissatisfaction)

Desire (impelling grounds, incentives)

Higher (intellectual, active, spontaneous)

Understanding (including the distinct powers of judgment, understanding, and reason)

Pleasure and displeasure, “satisfactions or dissatisfactions which depend on the manner in which we cognize the objects through concepts”

Motives, motive grounds (including both pure and impure motives)

Lower (sensible, passive, receptive)

Sensibility (including distinct powers of the senses and imagination)

“satisfactions and dissatisfactions which depend on the manner in which we are [sensibly] affected by objects” (28: 254)

Stimuli, motive causes, impulses.

 

            Kant’s defense of this complex taxonomy takes place on several levels. Most generally, Kant sides with Crusius against Wolff with respect to the reducibility of mental phenomena to a single overarching faculty. In a discussion of the science of bodies, Kant defends a broadly “Newtonian” as opposed to “Cartesian” approach to the study of natural phenomena. Descartes “explains all [physical] phenomena from the shape and the general motive power of bodies” while Newton’s “more satisfactory” method allows the assumption of “certain basic powers . . . from which the phenomena are derived” (29:935-6, cf. A649-50/B677-8). Kant allows that Descartes proposes a noble ideal for science, explaining that “all physics, of bodies as well as of minds, the latter of which is called psychology, amounts to this: deriving diverse powers, which we know only through observations, as much as possible from basic powers” (28:564, cf. 8:180-1; 28:210; 29:773-822; A648-9/B676-7). But Kant also adds that one must avoid excessive reduction of powers. The actual phenomena that one finds in the world – both the physical world of bodies and the mental interior world – require more than a single basic power. Thus Kant’s focus is on not overly reducing mental powers:

E.g., the imagination in the human being is an effect that we cognize to be not the same with other effects of the mind. Therefore the power related to this effect can only be called a power of the imagination (as a basic power). Likewise, under the title moving forces, repulsive force and attractive force are basic powers. Several have thought that they had to assume a single basic power for the sake of the unity of the substance and even have thought to gain cognition of it simply by coining the common title [KP14] of various basic powers, e.g. that the basic power of the soul is the power of representing the world. This would be the same as if I were to say: the sole basic power of matter is moving force, since repulsion and attraction both stand under the common concept of movement, yet one desires to know whether the former could also be derived from the latter, which is impossible. (8:181n)

While we must of course seek to find more fundamental basic powers, we are not justified in pretending that the forces of gravity and magnetism or of imagination and will are in fact reducible to a single basic power. Kant insists, “there must be several [basic powers] because we cannot reduce everything to one” (29:773-822).[28]

            With respect to Kant’s most important distinctions – between the three basic faculties of soul and between higher and lower faculties – Kant largely draws from earlier analyses to defend the irreducibility of these mental states. Kant seems to see the distinction between cognition and desire as straightforward, once one abandons the requirement of a unified and wholly reductive psychology. Still, following Crusius and xxx, he argues that cognition and desire are distinct both because not all cognitions give rise to desires (or aversions) (29:877-8) and because of the basic functions of cognition and desire are distinct: cognitions represent the world, while desires effect change in the world through action. Isolating feeling as a faculty distinct from both desire and sensation is a more important move for Kant. While Sulzer, Mendelssohn, and Baumgarten provided important background, Kant clearly argues from our experience of aesthetic pleasure to the claim that pleasure is a faculty distinct from cognition and desire because one can feel pleasures that go beyond mere cognition but that do not actually give rise to desire. Finally, the distinction between higher and lower faculties is a crucial psychological correlate to much of Kant’s work in his transcendental philosophy. While it is important to keep these projects distinct, Kant’s distinction between concepts and intuitions in his Critical philosophy both informs and is informed by his claim that the faculty of cognition has a higher, intellectual set of powers and a lower, sensuous set of powers that are irreducible to one another. By making this distinction, Kant xxx.  Flesh this section out based on how much I say about this in the last chapter. Xxx also reference article in Kain book (by Caygill). xxx

            In the end, then, Kant not only sides with those who sought to move away from Wolff’s reductivist single-faculty psychology, he also offers the most sophisticated arguments and the most clear and complete taxonomy of the mind available in late 18th century Germany. For a philosopher best known for his work on a priori arguments in epistemology and ethics, the richness of Kant’s contribution to the empirical study of human mental faculties is striking. xxx

 

3. Causal Laws Governing Human Beings

Kant did not discuss the structure of human mental faculties simply to argue against Wolff’s reduction of the mind to a single faculty of representation. Unlike Crusius, he also did not distinguish faculties in order to thereby establish his ethics based on a volitional faculty distinct from the faculty of cognition. And unlike Tetens, he did not expect his complex psychology to provide the foundation for his whole philosophy (though the tripartite structure of the mind did, as we pointed out in the last chapter, provide a framework for Kant’s three transcendental Critiques). For Kant, getting clear on the different faculties of the human mind is crucial for the sake of a full empirical psychology because “the concept of cause lies in the concept of power” (28:564) and in psychology we seek “natural laws of the thinking self” based on “observations about the play of our thoughts” (A347/B405, cf. 25:472). That is, each distinct mental power will be governed by its own causal laws (including laws governing how it relates to other mental powers), and a complete empirical psychology will involve an account of the laws governing the various causal powers of the human being both separately and in relation to each other.[29]

            For Kant, the different faculties of the soul are causally related to each other ordered such that

Pleasure precedes the faculty of desire, and the cognitive faculty precedes pleasure . . . .  [W]e can desire or abhor nothing which is not based on pleasure or displeasure.  For that which gives me no pleasure, I also do not want.  Thus pleasure or displeasure precedes desire or abhorrence.  But still I must first cognize what I desire, likewise what gives me pleasure or displeasure; accordingly, both are based on the cognitive faculty (29:877-8).[30]

Moreover, “all desires have a relation to activity and are the causality thereof” (25:1514, cf. 29:1024), and Kant even claims that desire plays the same role in psychology that motive forces (momentum, etc) play in physics (25:577).[31] Thus for any human action, there is a sequence of causes that can be traced as follows:

Cognition à Feeling of pleasure (or pain) à Desire à Action

At any step along this progression, the causal chain could be cut off. For example, when a normal human being tastes a mango (cognition), that taste gives pleasure (feeling), that pleasure causes a desire for the mango, and that desire leads one to eat (or continue eating) the mango. But when a normal human being sees a beautiful flower (cognition), this sight gives rise to pleasure, but that pleasure is “disinterested,” that is, it gives rise to no subsequent desire. And when one learns that the capital of Iceland is Reykjavik, one has a cognition, but this cognition (generally) gives rise to no pleasure and hence no desire.[32]

            This overall sketch, of course, requires a lot of filling in. In particular, Kant needs to explain what gives rise to cognitions in human beings, how and when those cognitions give rise to pleasures, and how and when those pleasures give rise to desires.[33] As Kant offers the details of all of these causal laws, his account gets extremely detailed, so here I only highlight aspects of his account. With respect to the lower faculty of cognition, Kant distinguishes between the five traditional senses (sight, hearing, touch, taste, and smell), the “inner sense” (our ability to “observe” our own inner mental states), and the imagination (which, for Kant, includes memory, foresight, and the imagination as a “fictive faculty” to think of things that we never experience). Kant does not say much about the five senses, laying out only the most general descriptions, such as that “the sense of touch lies in the fingertips and the nerve endings (papillae) and enables us to discover the form of a solid body by means of contact with its surface” (7:155) and that sight, touch, and hearing are “mechanical” while taste and smell are “chemical” (25:495). With respect to lower faculties of cognition, the imagination gets the most extensive causal treatment, and Kant posits that the imagination is governed by three fundamental laws: affinity, forming intuitions in space, and association.[34] The last of these, for example, is the principle that “empirical ideas that have frequently followed one another produce a habit in the mind such that when one idea is produced, the other also comes into being” (7:176; cf. 25: xxx, xxx, xxx; 28:236, 585, 673, 739; 29:883). Thus hearing a particular song may trigger thoughts of the person with whom one often listened to that song, or the thought of a certain book may cause one to think of the place where one read that book. The imagination also figures centrally in Kant's account of language: it is by virtue of customary association between sounds and thoughts that those sounds (and eventually written words) come to stand as symbols for those thoughts.

            Kant’s discussion of the higher faculty of cognition is more complex. This faculty is subdivided into three basic powers: reason, the understanding, and judgment: “quote on the roles of each of these” xxx. The power of judgment operates according to the principles governing analogy[35] – “things . . . which . . . agree in much, also agree in what remains” – and induction – “what belongs to many things of a genus belongs to the remaining ones too” (9:133, see too 24: 772). The understanding generates certain concepts as an immediate consequence of sensory perceptions, but most concepts of the understanding are generated through chains of comparison, reflection, and abstraction. With respect to the former, Kant argues that “on the occasion of experience” certain “concepts have arisen through the understanding, according to its nature” (28:233), such as the basic concepts of causation and substance that make it possible for our experience to be intelligible as experience of an objective world. Even these only become articulated as such[KP15]  through a process of “reflection” (28:233) on the experience that they help to structure. With respect to more empirical concepts, Kant explains how, for example, the sensory cognition of “a spruce, a willow, and a linden” can lead one to

compare[e] these objects with one another [and] note that they are different from one another in regard to the trunk, the branches, the leaves, etc.; but next . . . reflect on that which they have in common among themselves, trunk, branches, and leaves themselves, and . . . abstract from the quantity, the figure, etc. of these; and thus . . . acquire a concept of a tree.  (Jasche Logic, 9:95; see too 24: 252-3, 753, 907)

Reason, finally, operates through principles of logic: the cognition of the premises of an argument give rise to a cognition of the conclusion of that argument. When I think about the facts that “Socrates is a human” and “All humans are mortal,” I am led to the thought that “Socrates is mortal.”

            So far, of course, Kant's account of how the higher faculties work also tracks well how they ought to work, but Kant knows that people’s higher faculties often do not function according to these ideal laws, and he develops an account of how “other activities of the soul . . . are connected with the judgments of the understanding” to generate a “mixed effect” that can be mistaken “to be a judgment of the understanding” (R2244, 16:283-4).[36] Such mixed effects are ultimately the result of what Kant calls “prejudices,” which function as alternative principles by which some cognitions give rise to others according to causes other than the understanding strictly speaking. For example, “the prejudice of the prestige of the age” leads some to favor the writers of antiquity more than they should, thereby “elevating the relative worth of their writings to an absolute worth” (9:79). For those affected by this prejudice, cognitions of claims associated with a particular ancient writer will immediately give rise to affirmation of those claims, a transition inexplicable in terms of properly functioning higher cognitive powers alone. Prejudices primarily arise from “imitation, custom, and inclination” (9:76), and Kant especially highlights the role of intellectual laziness in cultivating prejudices. Of course, prejudices do not wholly displace higher cognitive faculties, but prejudices provide a way for Kant to make sense causally of transitions between beliefs that are not actually justified, and thus cannot be explained in terms of the higher cognitive faculties strictly speaking. This account of prejudice, supplemented with detailed accounts of various prejudices and an account of how the higher and lower faculties of cognition relate, make up his overall account of the faculty of cognition.

 

            Kant's account of the faculty of the feeling of pleasure and displeasure is the most original, complex, and confusing aspect of his faculty psychology. The originality lies in Kant's claim the faculty of feeling can be reduced to neither cognition nor volition, and Kant's basis for this claim is his account of aesthetic pleasure. Even those who argued against Wolff’s attempt to reduce all the basic powers of the soul to a single one generally ended up describing feeling pleasure as either a subjective form of cognition like color or scent (e.g. xxx or xxx) or as a constitutive part of desire (e.g. xxx or xxx). But Kant explains,

We have pleasure or displeasure without desiring or abhorring, e.g. if we see a beautiful area, then it enchants us, be we will not on that account wish at once to possess it.  Pleasure or displeasure is thus something entirely different from the faculty of desire. (29:877)

Kant’s point here can also be tied to his more general claim that asdf

What does it actually mean for pleasure to be a distinct basic power? First, pleasure for Kant is not merely a component part of volition. While Kant insists that all desire depends upon feeling, and even that most feelings of pleasure will be intimately linked with desires, the feeling of pleasure is distinct from both the desire with which it is linked and the cognition that gives rise to it. To whatever extent we might want to think of volitional components or cognitive components of feelings, no feeling can, for Kant, be reduced to these components. Second, this insistence upon its distinctive status requires that Kant articulate an account of precisely what the faculty of feeling is in its own right. Pleasures cannot merely be “the feelings that cause desires,” since not all pleasures do cause desires. Nor can pleasures just be a kind of sensation of the world, since pleasure is not reducible to cognition.[37]

 

            And in fact, Kant does offer both a general account of the nature of feeling and details about the causes and effects of feelings. One thing should be immediately noted: while Kant does allow that there are radically different kinds of feelings, he holds that all feelings are, in some sense, feelings of pleasure or displeasure. Thus Kant will often use “pleasure and displeasure” as synonymous with “feeling.” Kant rejects the dominant (at the time) Leibnizian-Wolffian definition of pleasure as “the [obscure] sensible representation of the perfection of an object” (20:226, cf. 5:227) and offers in its place at least two important “definitions” of his own:

(1) “The consciousness of the causality of a representation with respect to the state of the subject for maintaining it in that state can here designate in general what is called pleasure[KP16] ” (5:220, cf. 20:230, xxxcheck: R556, 15:241; 25:459, 785; 28: 247, 586; 29:890; 6:212, 7:231)

(2) “Pleasure is the representation of the agreement of an object or of an action with the subjective conditions of life” (5:9n; cf. 5:204; check xxx R567, 15:246, R586, 15:252, R1838-9, 16:133, 25:167-8, 181, 1501; 7:231; 28:247, 586, 29:891).

First, then, pleasure is defined simply as a mental state (a “representation”) oriented towards preserving itself. The feeling of pleasure just is a mental state in which one wants [KP17] to remain, while feelings of displeasure are feelings of wanting to be in a different state. But Kant connects this feeling of wanting to remain in one’s state with the concept of “life,” which he connects with self-activity and sometimes defines as a “faculty of a being to act in accordance with laws of the faculty of desire” (5:9n, cf. 28:275).[38] In the case of human beings, Kant identifies “life” with the full set of mental powers of cognition, feeling, and desire (28:xxx). The general idea here is that when one’s something promotes the activity of one’s powers, one gets a distinctive mental state that reflects this advancement of activity; this mental state is called “pleasure[KP18] .” When something inhibits one’s activity, one feels displeasure. In a lecture on metaphysics, Kant connects these two definitions:

The feeling of the promotion of life is pleasure, and the feeling of the hindrance of life is displeasure. Pleasure is when a representation contains a ground for being determined, for producing again the same representation, or for continuing it when it is there. (28:586)[39]

Thus we might say that when one feels pleasure, one feels like continuing in one’s state because one’s state is conducive to the activity of all one’s powers. When one feels displeasure one feels like ending one’s state because one’s state is an inhibition of activity. Strictly speaking, these definitions are best understood such that the first literally defines pleasure and pain, while the second explains these powers teleologically. That is, one has a feeling[u19]   

            Given his overall definition(s) of pleasure, Kant divides the possible objects of pleasure into different categories. Most fundamentally, and central to Kant's insistence that pleasure is not merely an aspect of desire, Kant claims that pleasures can be distinguished into those that give rise to desires and those that do not.[40] The key to this distinction is that desires are “objective” in that they are directed towards bringing about their objects in the world, while pleasures, in themselves, are wholly subjective, both in that they reflect something subjective about the subject (whether one’s overall mental state [KP20] is conducive to life) and in that they aim to preserve themselves subjectively (as mental states[KP21] ). But generally, preserving one’s pleasurable mental states will require acquiring those objects or objective states of affairs that bring one pleasure. If one experiences pleasure at the taste of a mango, one will need to continue eating the mango in order to continue experiencing the pleasure. Thus pleasure, in order to “produce again the same representation or . . . continue it” (28:586) must give rise to a desire, a mental state that actually affects the world by causing one to continue eating the mango. Kant calls these sorts of pleasures “interested” or “practical” pleasures, and such pleasures are always connected with desire. But Kant proposes that some pleasures are not interested and do not depend upon the actual presence of their objects. Kant suggests, for example,

We have pleasure or displeasure without desiring or abhorring, e.g., if we see a beautiful area, then it enchants us, but we will not on that account wish to possess it. Pleasure or displeasure is thus something entirely different from the faculty of desire. (29:878)

Lest one think, in this case, that such a pleasure is practical in the sense that at least one desires to remain in the presence of the beautiful area, Kant emphasizes (elsewhere),

Xxxquote from ku xxx.

In these cases, the source of one’s pleasure arises purely from reflection, and the actuality of the object of one’s reflection is not necessary in order to promote the “free play of the powers of representation” (5:217) that grounds the feeling of pleasure. Kant's aesthetics (discussed briefly in chapter three) is focused on a transcendental account of these disinterested pleasures. For the purpose of his empirical account, his main purpose is to show that there are such pleasures.

            With the exception of aesthetic feelings, then, pleasures sustain themselves by means of the faculty of desire. The faculty of desire is, in many respects, the most complicated faculty in terms of its causal laws, and explaining it fully requires a discussion of the biological roots of causal laws in Kant’s account. In general, though, the faculty of desire is “the faculty to be, by means of one’s representations, the cause of the objects of those representations” (5:9n, 6:211) or “the self-determination of a subject’s power through the representation of something in the future as an effect of this representation” (7:251). The key point here is that desire is a mental state by virtue of which one becomes a cause of the objects of that mental state. Whereas cognition merely thinks about its objects and feeling merely enjoys its objects, desire actually brings about its objects[KP22] . To desire something is to have the requisite mental state for bringing that thing about. Even when desire is not fully self-conscious (as in animals, or as with bare urges) or when it is merely a response to sensory stimuli, it still represents a mental state directed towards an object as a cause of bringing that object about. Even when animals (or we) do not understand what is attractive about an object, the sensation of an object can still bring about a desire for it. When desires are more deliberate and self-conscious, when they follow from the higher faculty of cognition such that we want something because we understand what it is, then Kant describes such desires as “a faculty to do or to refrain from doing as one pleases” (6:213). And Kant of course recognizes that when one has a desire, one might also lack the ability to actually bring about the end of that desire. A desire, for Kant, always involves a volitional commitment to an object, but when one is committed to bringing about the object while still recognizing that one lacks the power to actualize that commitment, one’s desire is called a mere “wish” (6:213). When one desires an object and is also aware of one’s physical [KP23] p[u24] ower to bring about that object, one “chooses” it (6:213). It should be clear, here, that “desire” is actually closer to what we consider “choice” than it is to what we typically consider “desire.” When a person “desires” something in Kant's sense, it means that they have the sort of mental state that will bring about its object as long as it can. Thus what we might consider an inactive “desire” would for Kant be merely an inactive ground for a possible desire. Kant explains, “Concupiscence (lusting after something) must be distinguished from desire itself, as a stimulus to determining desire. Concupiscence is always a sensible modification of the mind but one that has not yet become an act of the faculty of desire” (6:213).

            Beyond this general description of desire, Kant must explain why it is that desires arise for certain objects and not others. Generally speaking, the account is fairly simple. Given a cognition that gives rise to a practical pleasure, one will experience a desire for the object of that pleasure[KP25] . The only problem, then is explaining why certain cognitions give rise to practical pleasures while others do not. Kant's solution to this problem is, justifiably, extremely complex for human beings. Generally speaking, he distinguishes between higher and lower faculties of desire based on whether they are moved by pleasures in higher cognitions (principles informed by concepts or ideas) or lower cognitions (brute sensations or imagination). But within these classifications, Kant must explain the variety of forms of human desire, and he articulates that account in the context of a description of the biological and environmental factors in defining human beings in general.

 

4) Human Natural Predispositions

            One of the central claims of Kant's philosophy of biology is his claim that “it would be absurd . . . to hope that there may yet arise a Newton who could make comprehensible even the generation of a blade of grass according to natural laws that no intention had ordered” (5:400). By denying even the hope of a biological Newton who might “adequately come to know the organized beings and the internal possibility in accordance with merely mechanical principles of nature” (5:400), Kant is rejecting, at least in practice, a major view within 18th century biology. During this time, there were two dominant approaches within biology for dealing with the emergence of organic structures, including the complex organization of human beings.[41] One, called “epigenesis,” was put forward by Descartes and held (in its strongest form) that matter self-organizes into complex living beings by mere interactions of physical forces.[42] The other, “preformationism,” was put forward in its classic form by Malebranche and held in its strongest form that living beings existed preformed in ancestral organisms, like little Russian dolls present in miniature in the eggs of Eve (or the sperm of Adam). This view was endorsed by most medical textbooks in the early 18th century. Both views had more subtle variations. Buffon, who Kant called “the great author of the system of nature” (7: 221) for his 44 volume Natural History, held an epigenesist view that saw organic beings emerging from matter, not by means of mere mechanism but via an “interior mold” in “organic matter.” [KP26] Kant's student Herder posited an epigenesist account based on a “living, organic power” (Ideen Bk. 7, ch. 4, in Sloan 2002: 242). And Charles Bonnet, a Swiss biologist influential in Germany, held that living beings were preformed, not in the sense that such beings literally preexisted as miniature versions of their eventual selves but in the sense that certain “seeds” or “germs” (Keime) preexist and develop into complex living beings. These two different approaches to biological organization, if applied to human mental powers, would yield very different conceptions of human science. An epigenesist anthropology would require showing how physical forces (or, for more complex epigenesists, “organic powers”) develop into human mental structures. For classic preformationists, all that would be required is an account of what mental structures one actually finds in human beings, since these could not be further explained.

            In rejecting a “Newton of a blade of grass,” Kant clearly rejects most forms of epigenesis, but he also aims to develop an account that is not strictly preformationist. Kant does not assume that humans are pre-existent in the egg or sperm of their most distant ancestors, formed in miniature and waiting to emerge. And while he makes use of the term “germ” (Keime), Kant's dominant category for thinking about biology in general and human biology in particular is the category of a “natural predisposition” (Naturanlage). This concept combines important aspects of both the epigenetic and preformationist views. Kant defines natural predispositions as “the grounds of a determinate unfolding which are lying in the nature of an organic body” (2:434),[43] and in this context he specifically argues that “chance or universal mechanical laws could not produce such agreements[KP27] , [so] we must consider such arrangements as preformed” (2:435). But Kant still insists not only that “outer things can well be occasioning causes” (2:435) for the development of these predispositions but also that “even in the case of the structure of an animal, it can be assumed that there is a single predisposition that has the fruitful adaptiveness to produce many different advantageous consequences” (2:126). Like epigenesists, in order words, Kant wants to explain the variety of natural organisms in terms of the smallest number of explanatory principles, but like preformationists, he is willing to allow that at least some elements of biological structure cannot be explained in terms of mechanism alone. Moreover, the way in which Kant suggests that outer things affect the development of natural predispositions ends up being selective rather than purely mechanical. That is, natural predispositions “lie ready . . . to be on occasion either unformed or restrained, so that [an organism] would become suited to his place in the world” (2:245). Kant's use of predispositions is thus a sort of proto-Darwinian account of biological (including human) development: various predispositions are given that develop in response to various environmental conditions in accordance with what is needed to thrive within those conditions.

            As Kant's work in the philosophy of biology develops, this account becomes more nuanced and less preformationist. In response to Herder’s quasi-epigenesist account according to which Herder dispenses with anything preformed by positing an “organic power” that forms matter into living beings, Kant claims to “fully concur” but adds a “reservation”:

that if the cause organizing itself from within were limited by its nature only perhaps to a certain number and degree of differences in the formation of a creature (so that after the institution of which it were not further free to form yet another type under altered circumstances), then one could call this natural determination [Naturbestimmung] of the forming nature also “germs” or “original predispositions,” without thereby regarding the former as primordially implanted machines and buds that unfold themselves only when occasioned (as in the system of [preformationism][44]), but merely as limitations, not further explicable, of a self-forming faculty, which latter we can just as little explain or make comprehensible. (8:62)

This concession to Herder makes clear that Kant does not consider himself a traditional preformationist, including even an outright denial of the language of “occasioning” outer causes that he used earlier (2:435). But Kant does not actually withdraw into anything like a traditional epigenesist account of organisms, and his Critique of Judgment (published two years after this review) emphasizes that his view still fits into a “system of generic preformation, since the productive capacity of the progenitor is still preformed” (5:423). But Kant uses the increasing complexity of epigenesist to clarify the primarily epistemic sense in which he understands his own preformationism. By appealing to “predispositions” in living beings, Kant does not intend to commit himself to any particular metaphysical conception of the development of living things. Instead, his goal is to emphasize an epistemic and methodological shift. Rather than seeking, as epigenesists often did, to give an account of the emergence of biological structures from simpler processes – whether Cartesian mechanical forces or some supposed single kind of organic matter (Buffon) or organic force (Herder) – Kant points out that our investigation of living beings proceeds best when we seek to discover the minimal number of predispositions from which we can explain the variety that we find. Metaphysically, preformationists are free to consider these predispositions as primordially implanted structures that unfold, and epigenesists are free to think of them as inexplicable limitations on the range of new structures that can epigenetically emerge in an organism. But humans lack the ability to explain basic predispositions in trermsterms of merely physical mechanisms, so they will also retain an irreducible epistemic role in the investigation of organic beings.

One corollary of the specifically epistemic (or regulative) use of predisposition is that Kant’s pessimism about there arising a  finding a Newton of a blade of grass is not a denial that the generation of a blade of grass must in fact be causally determined according to natural laws. Kant insists, “the principle that everything that we assume to belong to nature (phaenomenon) and to be a product of it must also be able to be conceived as connected with it in accordance with mechanical laws nonetheless remains in force” (5:422). And even in scientific inquiry, we have an “obligation to give a mechanical explanation of all products and events in nature, even the most purposive, as far as our capacity to do so” (5:415, cf. 5:411). But Kant supposes that human beings will find themselves unable, ultimately, to reduce all natural predispositions to mechanical causes.

And this gives rise to a further aspect of Kant's biology:[45] as a “heuristic principle for researching the particular laws of nature” (5:411), one can add to the principle of mechanical causation a “principle of final causes” (5:387) “in order to supplement the inadequacy of [mechanical explanation] in the empirical search for particular laws of nature” (5:383).  According this heuristic principle, “nothing in [an organized product of nature] is in vain, purposeless, or to be ascribed to a blind mechanism of nature” (5:376). By relegating his biology to the status of a heuristic, a “maxim of the reflecting power of judgment” (5:398) that “is merely subjectively valid” (5:390), Kant is free to adopt a biology that explains natural organisms in terms of purposive structures. The predispositions are not further explainable either physically (through mechanist epigenesis) or metaphysically (through divinely ordained preformationism) are susceptible to a scientific, teleological analysis. One can biologically explain why these developmental possibilities and not others are present is through explaining what purpose they serve.      

Overall, Kant's epistemic preformationism in biology has several important implications for his empirical anthropology. First, it allows Kant to forego the necessity of providing an account of how human predispositions came into existence. As he explains in his “Conjectures on the Beginning of Human History,” “we must begin with something that human reason cannot derive from prior natural causes – that is, with the existence of human beings,” including all of their natural predispositions (8:110). The work of Kant's empirical anthropology, then, will primarily be to reduce given powers to as few natural predispositions as possible, to explain the environmental factors that allow certain predispositions (but not others) to flourish in (certain) human beings, and then to use this small number of natural predispositions to explain what we observe of human beings. Second, Kant's emphasis on teleological explanation of these predispositions gives him additional resources for “explaining” predispositions without mechanistically explaining them.[46] Thus Kant explains that Give e.g.s (7:175)  . . . (7:274).

Third, Kant's preformationism contributes to a his general disinterest in giving materialist explanations of psychological predispositions. Kant contrasts his own approach to empirical anthropology with that of Ernst Platner, a doctor and contemporary who developed an anthropology based on what Kant called “subtle, and . . . eternally futile inquiries as to the manner in which bodily organs are connected with thought” (10:145). To some extent, this disinterest is due to his despair of complete mechanistic accounts of predispositions and interest in teleological ones. To some extent, it is due to Kant's pessimism about the state of neuroscience in the 18th century. Thus Kant refers to the fact that “physicians and physiologists in general are still not advanced enough to see deeply into the mechanical element in the human being” (7:214), and he rejects physiological approaches to mental phenomena largely because one “does not know the cranial nerves and fibers, nor does he understand how to put them to use for his purposes” (7:119, see too 7:176). Where doctors have developed reliable accounts of mental phenomena, Kant is perfectly willing to accept these (see, e.g., 7:213, 220; 15:943, 947). And Kant even speculates on his own about chemical processes in “the water of the brain” that might underlie the processes of “separating and combining given sensory representations” (12:34). But ultimately[u28] , Kant also has a principled objection to any attempt to completely reduce mental powers to physical processes, which is that “the soul can perceive itself only through the inner sense” (12:35), whereas the physical body is always spatially located[KP29] . Thus, the most that physiological explanation could ever do it to explain “the matter that makes possible” mental phenomena. Mental phenomena as such will always have a character that is irreducible to the physical. Xxx bring in stuff from metahphysics lectures too.xxx[47]

 

In sum, Kant's empirical anthropology focuses on the explanation of diverse mental phenomena in terms of as few basic powers as possible, tracing these basic powers back to purposive natural predispositions that develop in the context of environmental influences.

 

5) Kant's Overall Empirical Account

Kant's account of natural predispositions provides the biological background for his empirical psychology in that Kant can take basic powers to be the developed forms of natural predispositions. The account of natural predispositions also provides a natural means by which Kant can explain the specific ways in which the faculties of (practical) pleasure and desire function in human beings. In general, for Kant, natural predispositions (or basic powers) function as the bases for connections between mental states, the grounds in the human being for the observed laws covering such connection. As Kant explains, we “may not at all concoct a priori basic powers . . . [because] we can only know a basic power through the relation of a cause to an effect” (8:180).[48] Thus for any two mental states, we can describe their connection in terms of a causal law that is grounded in a basic power, which is itself the determinate unfolding of a natural predisposition.

Mental State 1 à Mental State 2

­­

Actualized Natural Predisposition

But the language of natural predisposition allows Kant to expand the sense of “basic power” beyond the limited and abstract structure of his empirical psychology. As we will see, in the context of the faculties of (practical) pleasure and desire, Kant develops a vocabulary of natural predispositions that plays the same role as basic powers but includes the flexibility and variety needed to make sense of the myriad different ways in which human beings can be motivated to actions.

With respect to the faculty of cognition, Kant’s treatment of natural predispositions is fairly straightforward. Each cognitive power is the expression of a distinct natural predisposition. Thus the senses, inner sense, the imagination, and the higher faculties of judgment, understanding, and reason are all different natural predisposition in the human being (KrVA66, MS 6:444-5, LA 25:1172, LMxxx 29:915). Humans have natural predispositions to sense, imagine, and think in accordance with the laws described above. Thus in explaining the connection between one cognition and another, one appeals to the natural predispositions active in effecting that transition. For example, the transition from the thought of one’s dog to the thought of dog food is effected by the imagination, so one could describe this transition as follows:

    Thought of dog à thought of dog-food

­­

Imagination (the predisposition governed by the law of association)[49]

 

By contrast, the transition from the thought of one’s dog to the thought “canine animal” would be effected by the understanding, hence the relevant predisposition would be different. In both cases, however, a complete explanation of the origin of a particular cognition must include, for Kant, not only the prior state that caused the cognition and the causal law according to which that state caused that transition, but also the natural predisposition that is the ground of that law.

            In this context, Kant is also able to offer an empirical response to David Hume’s famous claim that there is no foundation in reason or the understanding for ideas such as those of causation or substance. Hume had famously argued that Xxx add a ¶ on Kant's empirical argument vs. Hume’s empiricism, i.e., certain sensations can cause concepts without determining the content of them, connect to KrV and last chapter xxx.

As already noted above, there are of course important variations amongst human beings in terms of the exercise of natural cognitive predispositions. Some of these are rooted in predispositions themselves, such as certain forms of mental illness. Others involve a deficiency in the development of natural predispositions. And others, including all prejudices, involve circumstances in which some predispositions (linked either to imagination or to the faculty of desire) override the understanding and reason, leading to erroneous judgments. There are also positive variations in cognitive powers, such as wit or originality of thought, which Kant calls calls “talents,” a sort of “excellence of the cognitive faculty which depends not on instruction but on the subject’s natural predisposition” (7:220). Altogether, Kant develops an account of cognitive predispositions that identifies the basic powers of cognition as predispositions and then accounts for variations in cognitive abilities through either hereditary or acquired defects in these predispositions or their expression.

 

Predispositions become even more important and complex, however, with respect to the faculty of desire and the practical pleasures related to one’s desires. As noted in the last section, the causal structure that determines whether a particular cognition will give rise to a desire or aversion in a human being can be exceedingly complex. Many things that give rise to desires in one person do not do so in others, things can give rise to desires sometimes and not other times, and human beings – even as objects of empirical study – seem capable of a kind of freedom of choice that might seem to preclude a naturalistic account. In every case, desires are preceded by cognitions that provoke feelings of pleasure that in turn provoke desires. But while virtually all feelings of pleasure cause desires for their objects (the only exceptions being the special cases of aesthetic pleasures), cognitions can cause pleasure, displeasure, or no feelings at all. Kant seeks to explain this complex volitional structure using a set of basic categories of desire, all fundamentally tied back to two basic kinds of natural predispositions: instincts (Instinkt) and propensities (Hang).

The nature and role of instincts is fairly straightforward. Among the natural predispositions present in human beings are a set of instincts that ground the connections between various cognitions and the practical pleasures (or pains) that give rise to desires (or aversions) to the objects of those cognitions. Given the distinctness between the faculties of feeling and desire, there would be, strictly speaking, separate predispositions underlying the connection between, on the one hand, a particular cognition and subsequent feeling, and, on the other hand, that feeling and its consequent desire. But because all practical pleasures give rise to desire and Kant has already offered an account of non-practical desires that explains how they cause feelings without subsequently generating desires, in his detailed account of human motivation, Kant does not distinguish between the power that grounds a connection between cognition and feeling and the power that grounds the connection between the feeling and desire. Instead, Kant ascribes the transition from cognition to desire to a single basic natural predisposition. (For ease of presentation, I sometimes drop the reference to the intermediary practical feeling in Kant's account and simply describe the role of natural predispositions as relating cognitions to desires.) In the case of instinct, Kant’s model of motivation maps straightforwardly onto his account of predispositions in general.

Cognition à Pleasure à Desire

                                               

   Instinct

For example,

Sweet smell of a ripe mango à Pleasure  à Desire for that mango

              

   Instinct for sweet foods

 

Often, instincts will become operative when one is in the presence of the object that one’s instinct predisposes one to desire (or avoid). Kant explains that “little chicks already have from nature an instinct of aversion to the hawk, of which they are afraid as soon as they merely see something fly in the air” (28:255). With respect to human beings, Kant even explains how our sense of smell, by means of “its affinity with the organ of taste” and “the latter’s familiar sympathy with the instruments of digestion,” serves as an “instinct” that “guided the novice . . . allow[ing] him a few things for nourishment but for[bidding] him others” as though it were a kind of “faculty of pre-sensation . . . of the suitability of or unsuitability of a food for gratification” (8:111). Central to these operations of instinct is that instincts ground connections between cognitions and anticipatory pleasures that give rise to desires. And these connections occur even before any experience of pleasures that might follow from the satisfaction of the desire. In cases where the objects of instincts are not present, Kant even suggests that instincts can be “directed to an indeter­minate object; they make us acquainted with the object” (25:584). As he illustrates,

One knows that children, who are hardly born, show an instinct for nutrition, without knowing what they need, and immediately carry out the art of the physical law to suckle the breast; if they did not have the instinct, but one first had to accustom them to this, then many would perish. . . . We can see that the sexual instinct is a natural instinct by the fact that, even if they were in the monastery, when [the time of] puberty comes, persons are still disturbed by the instinct, and feel the need for an object which they do not yet know. (25:584)

Thus one can have instincts with definite objects of present awareness, but one can also have instincts with indeterminate and unknown objects, instincts that agitate to activity in such a way that one comes into the presence of their objects. Moreover, the power of imagination can greatly expand the scope of instinct. In his “Conjectures on the Beginning of Human History,” Kant describes a scene where “a fruit which, because it looked similar to other available fruits which he had previously tasted, encouraged him to make the experiment” of eating it (8:111).[50] Given an association between a particular visual experience and a particular olfactory experience, a similar visual experience will – by virtue of the laws that govern the imagination – give rise to an imaginative idea that corresponds to that olfactory experience. Given a sufficiently strong instinctual connection between that olfactory experience and practical pleasure, the mere sight of a similar fruit will give rise to a desire to consume that fruit.

 

Even with this expanded conception of instinct, however, the vast majority of human life is not directly governed by instinct, for two important reasons. First, many of the things that human beings desire are not reducible to particular instincts. The human desires for the company of one’s friends, wearing fashionable clothes, resting on comfortable sofas, watching one’s favorite television programs, attending baseball games, and even for things like smoking cigarettes and eating fine foods, cannot be explained by appeal to brute instincts. These are all, in varying degrees, connected with habits that give rise to desires for certain objects. Second, even when we pursue objects for which we have instincts, humans typically do not pursue those objects directly from instinct. Our instincts give rise to what we might call a desire, but then we have a capacity to reflect on whether or not to pursue the object of that desire. And often one decides not to follow through on an instinct for the sake of something else, often something for which one does not have a particularly strong instinctual desire at that moment. When I decide not to eat that delicious mango because I know that it will make me sick later, I do not act from any instinctual desire for long term health. If humans merely acted from instinct, the task of explaining human motivation would merely require a catalog of the relevant instincts and a careful description of the environment in which those instincts play out. But human behavior is, as Kant recognized, much harder to explain.

            One might be tempted, at this point, to appeal to human freedom as a reason for the difficulty of explaining human behavior. And many have thought that the complexity of human motivation provides some support for Kant’s account of freedom.[51] But within his empirical anthropology, Kant takes the complexity of human action not as a reason to posit any kind of transcendental human freedom, but rather as a basis for a much more complicated but still wholly empirical anthropology. Kant adds the requisite complexity through a generous use of the category of a “propensity.” In one lecture, Kant defines a propensity as a “natural predisposition” that provides “the inner possibility of an inclination” (25:1111-2; cf. 7:265, 25:1517). More generally, a propensity is a natural predisposition that does not itself provide a ground for connections between cognitions and practical pleasures (and thereby desires), but that makes it possible for the human being, in the context of environmental factors, to develop a ground for such connections. Having introduced this notion of a propensity, Kant puts it to use to address the two problems mentioned in the previous paragraph.

First, Kant focuses on human propensities for “inclinations,” which Kant identifies as “habitual grounds of desire” (25:1114) and which, for the purposes of his empirical anthropology, are distinguished from instincts.[52][53] Like instincts, inclinations provide bases for connections between cognitions and desires. Unlike instincts, however, inclinations are not natural predispositions but rather are tendencies that are brought about in human beings through certain experiences. For example,

[A]ll savages have a propensity for intoxicants; for although many of them have no acquaintance at all with intoxication, and hence absolutely no desire for the things that produce it, let them try these things but once, and there is aroused in them an almost inextinguishable desire for them. (6:29; cf. 25:1112, 1339, 1518)[54]

In some cases, one needs only a single experience of an object for an inclination to be awakened. Generally, however, inclinations require “frequent repetition” (25:1514) to develop the kind of habit for it that can ground future desires. Kant even seems to suggest that there is a sort of propensity to develop habits, such that when one experiences something consistent over a long period of time, one develops an inclination for it (cf. 9:xxx pedagogy). In any case of inclination, however, it is not enough to simply have exposure to something to develop an inclination for it. Experiences give rise only to inclinations when human beings already have requisite propensities. The model for explaining human action in those cases looks like:

 

Sensory cognition      à     Feeling/Desire

(sight or smell of strong drink)           (desire to consume the drink)

­­     

Past experience (with strong drink)   à  Inclination (for strong drink)

                                                       

                                    Propensity (for strong drink[KP30] )

 

In these cases, the immediate explanation for why a particular cognition gives rise to a practical pleasure and thereby a desire will be similar to the case of instinct, but because inclinations are not themselves innate, the account requires an extra level of complexity. And this complexity provides for much of the richness and diversity that one finds in human desires. Fancy clothes, comfortable sofas, cigarettes, and baseball are all possible objects of inclination, even when we have no instinctual need for them. And because humans differ in their experiences, even those with the same propensities (and Kant allows for some, but not much, variation in basic human propensities) will end up with very different patterns of desire. Because propensities are natural predispositions, Kant does not need to give a specific mechanical account for them, but he does aim to reduce the number of posited propensities to as few as possible, and ideally he would seek to provide teleological explanations for each propensity.

            Moreover, Kant suggests that the cultivation of inclination generally involves pleasure in way that goes beyond mere instinct. For both instincts and inclination, the experience of the object of one’s desire will bring with it a subsequent pleasure that must be distinguished from the practical pleasure that causes the desire. In the case of instincts, however, this subsequent pleasure plays no explanatory role in the development of the instinct. The instincts for nursing or for sex motivate human beings to seek milk or sex not merely because one has experienced their pleasures already. Instincts are pre-sensations (8:111) of pleasure. But in the case of inclinations, the anticipatory practical pleasure that gives rise to desires generally follows from past experiences of the pleasure that one experiences when one attains the objects of desire. One accidentally experiences some object, gets pleasure from the experience, and thus forms an inclination that grounds future connections between the cognition of that object and the desire to experience it. One might taste an intoxicating beverage out of thirst (rather than a desire for intoxicants), for example, or might literally fall into a pleasantly cool pool of water on a hot day. When the experience of such objects brings pleasure, one will seek intoxicating beverages even when one is not thirsty, or one will deliberately seek out and immerse oneself in cool pools of water. In these cases, we might specify the past experience as past experience of pleasure in the objects. Of course, one need not always experience pleasure in order to form an inclination. One who has started smoking can find herself craving cigarettes even while the actual experience of smoking is still generally unpleasant, and one who develops a habit of acting in a particular way can develop an inclination to continue acting in that way, even if it is not, in itself, particularly pleasurable. (For this reason, Kant recommends that parents not accustom their children to particular xxx, xxx, or xxx, lest they develop habits that are hard to break.)

 

The addition of inclinations to Kant's account of human motivation greatly enriches that account, and it makes it possible to explain why there is such a wide range of divergent human interests. But inclinations, like instincts, still do not seem to involve the kind of reflective desires that characterize much of human action. Kant captures this limitation by ascribing both instinct and inclination to the “lower” faculty of desire. Both affect human beings insofar as we are motivated by sensory or imaginative mental states, but not insofar as we govern our actions by means of concepts and principles. To make sense of these kinds of desires, to which Kant assigns the term “choice” (6:213, xxx, xxx), Kant appeals to yet another propensity, a propensity to what he calls “character.”

Kant uses the term character in several senses throughout his writings. In the broadest sense, the character of a thing is the “law of its causality, without which it would not be a cause at all,” such that “every effective cause must have a character” (A539/B567, cf. 25:634).[55] In this sense, gravity reflects the “character” of matter, and one’s instincts are part of the “character” of one’s lower faculty of desire.  In a quite different sense, Kant uses “character,” in the context of one’s “intelligible character,” to refer to the free ground – “which is not itself appearance” – of one’s appearances in the world (A539/B567).  Character in this sense has no role to play in empirical explanations of action, although Kant will end up arguing that this intelligible character grounds the empirical character of the higher faculty of desire.[56]  The character that plays an important role in Kant’s empirical theory of the higher faculty of desire is distinct from though grounded in intelligible character, and more specific than the character of an efficient cause in general. Kant defines this sense of character as “that property of the will by which the subject has tied himself to certain practical principles” (7:292) or “a certain subjective rule of the higher faculty of desire” (25:438[57]), and this sense of character plays the same role for the higher faculty of desire that instincts and inclinations play for the lower.[58] As Kant explains, “the man of principles, from whom we know for sure what to expect, not from his instinct, for example, but from his will, has character” (7:285, cf. 25:1514). One can describe such motivations as follows:

     Cognition (of a principle for action) à Pleasure/Desire

 

Character

“Character” is a matter of commitment to various principles (cf. xxx), or “maxims” of action.[59] Thus, one may have a commitment to the principle “early to bed, early to rise.”  In such a case, one’s actions might be explained as follows:

         “Early to bed…” à Desire to go to bed

       

Fixed commitment to “Early to bed, early to rise”

Of course, this example is too simple in several respects.  For one thing, the cognition of the principle “Early to bed, early to rise” is not in itself sufficient to generate the desire to go to bed, since one must also have some awareness of the fact that it is early evening – time for bed – rather than early morning – time to rise. One’s perception of one’s situation – the sky is growing darker, the clock says 9 PM, etc – brings to mind the relevant principle,[60] and one’s character ensures that the principle will be efficacious in generating its corresponding action.

            Moreover, one’s commitment to the principle “early to bed, early to rise” is itself the result of other causes. In particular, Kant needs an account of the causes of character as such, that is, the ability to act in accordance with principles at all; and he also needs an account of the origins of the particular principles upon which individuals act. With respect to the first point, Kant's account of character development is similar to his account of the development of inclinations. There is a “propensity to character” (25:1172, cf. 25:651, 823, 1176) that is actualized by various experiences (cf. 25:1172; cf. 7:294), such that one might have the propensity but lack character, just as one might have a propensity to intoxicants but never develop the inclination. In the case of character, however, habit does not play a role in its formation.[61] Instead, Kant emphasizes the role of education (25:1172), examples (7:294), and “moral discourses” (25:1173n1, cf. too 9: xxx pedagogy xxx), and he gives specific recommendations regarding the kinds of education that are most effective, such as education that avoids “imitation” (25:635, cf. 7:325; 5:154; 25:599, 722ff., 1386). Beyond these direct influences, Kant suggests that oblique factors can play a powerful role in character cultivation, such as stable and just political regimes, peace, and even progress in the arts and sciences. He even suggests that politeness cultivates character by combating passions and promoting self-control.[62] And finally, Kant points out that other natural predispositions (especially temperament, which I discuss in more detail in chapter six) can facilitate the development of character (cf. 7:285, 290; 25:1388). All of these elements work together to develop what is a mere propensity into an active ability to govern oneself according to conscious principles rather than reactive instincts and inclinations.

            Many of the influences responsible for the development of character as such also contribute to the development of the specific principles by which one acts, but Kant also emphasizes that most of these principles are only “intellectual . . . in some respect <secundum quid>” because they “rest on sensibility, and . . . merely the means for arriving at the end are presented by the understanding” (28:589). For example, the principle above – “early to bed . . .” – is likely a principle that one learns through instruction, but this instruction is effective because it proposes plausible principles for satisfying one’s instincts and inclinations. Even in the absence of specific instruction, in fact, one is capable of understanding the nature of the world, and one can thereby form principles of action based on what sorts of action will best promote one’s instincts and inclinations. Such principles will be intellectual (rather than sensible) causes of desire, but they still “rest on sensibility” because one formulates them only in the context of the inclinations and instincts that govern one’s lower faculty of desire. And [KP31] Kant thinks that generally even actions that might be described as following “from inclination” are really grounded in a character committed to principles that make the objects of inclination its ends.[63] Generally it is not the case that my inclination for sweet food directly causes me to eat it; rather, I understand that eating this food will satisfy my felt inclination, and (because of my character) this thought causes me to eat it.

            Most human actions, motivated by these kinds of “impure” principles of character, can be explained only by an extremely complicated motivational picture. First, sensory data get transformed into an understanding of one’s situation based on concepts due to the operation of natural higher cognitive powers. This understanding then gives rise to the thought of one of more practical principles based on the details of one’s understanding of one’s situation as well as of one’s instincts and inclinations. Thus one who recognizes the darkening sky under the concept of “early evening” might be led to think of the principle “early to bed…” by virtue of understanding this as the time at which going to bed will best facilitate the satisfaction of various inclinations over the long term. These practical principles give rise to practical pleasures and thereby desires – which Kant, in these cases, calls “choices” – by means of one’s character. This character in general is formed through education, social-cultural influences, and one’s own past behavior, and the way in which particular thoughts of principles give rise to practical pleasures is determined by the details of these character-forming influences as well as by the cooperating or hindering influence of inclinations (which are themselves formed by past experiences) and instincts. Both character in general and the inclinations that largely determine the content of the principles on which one acts are grounded in natural propensities The result is that human beings, due partly to different natural propensities but largely to different past experiences, will be motivated by similar sensory data to behave in radically different ways.

            As complicated as this picture is, Kant thinks that human motivation is even more complicated, for three important reasons. First, the account given above assumes that for any given set of sensory data, there is only one way in which one’s natural powers can conceptualize that content and, more importantly, that this conceptualization only lends itself to a single practical principle. But it might well be that the recognition of the darkening sky is conjoined with a recollection of an invitation to a social gathering that promises to be particularly enjoyable. Here one may be led to think of the principle “early to bed, early to rise” but also the principle “don’t forgo opportunities for enjoyable social gatherings” (cf. 6:473, 7:277-82), when one cannot in fact act in ways that follow from both practical principles. In such cases, even one with a well-formed character will have conflicting possible grounds of action. One’s character could enable the former principle to give rise to a practical pleasure that would motivate one to stay home, or it could enable the latter principle to give rise to a practical pleasure that would motivate one to go out[KP32] . From the inside-out standpoint of practical reflection, of course, what one does is a matter of free choice. But from the standpoint of empirical psychology, it requires a psychological explanation. Kant first insists that “in empirical psychology, wholly equal incentives cannot be thought” (28:678; cf. 25:278) because in the case of equal incentives, there would be no choice and thus no action (29:902). As a result, one can distinguish between what Kant calls “living” and “dead” underlying grounds (or powers). Even when one has only a “dead” ground, however, one might still be left with something like a desire, with what Kant calls a “wish[u33] ,” where the “ground determining one to action . . . is [not] joined with one’s consciousness of the ability to bring about its object” (6:213), given one’s pursuit of one’s other ends. Thus one goes to bed because one’s overall character subordinates the principle of socialization with the principle of prudent rest, but one falls to sleep wishing that one could somehow both go to bed early and partake in the enjoyable party.

            The second added complication to this account of choice is that although strictly speaking character requires commitment to act from consistent principles, very few human beings have character in this fully developed sense. Kant specifically mentions the difficulty that one might have with the practical maxim “early to bed, early to rise” in one his lectures:

who is not steadfast in this, often lays hold of a resolve, for which he knows for sure that nothing will come of it, because he knows that he has already often broken reso­lutions. Then the human being is in his [own] eyes a wind-bag. He no longer has any confidence in himself; from this arises hopelessness . . . This is how it is with things for which one wants to break one’s habit of doing them, for example, sleeping in; then it is always said, just this one time more, but then no more, and thus one again philosophizes oneself free of one’s plan . . . one must seek to keep one’s word to oneself just as conscientiously as to others. From this arises a firm confidence in ourselves. Who knows how to manage himself so that he can be content with himself, is stead­fast. (25:624)

Of course, in some cases of acting against one’s principles, inclinations directly overpower one’s higher faculty of desire, such that one will, in the strict sense, act on the basis of inclination alone, without the reflection that characterizes choice. Such cases will be quite rare, but in such cases, one’s higher faculty of desire as a whole is the sort of “dead” power described in the last paragraph. More often, one’s inclination corrupts the grounds of one’s choice, as here, where one “philosophizes oneself free of one’s plan.” And for Kant, this tendency is quite common. Kant claims that character in this strict sense “is fixed very late” or “comes at a ripe old age” (25:654, 1385, cf. 7: 294). Most people have a kind of “bad character” (schlechte Character; 25:650, 1172) or “flawed character” (25:1172). Here “character” refers to a “constitution of these higher powers” (25:227) according to which, rather than acting on the basis of fixed principles, one allows the principles on the basis of which one chooses to vary depending on the particular configuration of inclinations present at the time of choice. In these cases, inclinations and instincts not only affect the practical principles to which one commits oneself in general but also determine whether and to what extent various practical principles play a role in one’s deliberation at a particular moment. Thus, one who has a firmly established character will decide, on the basis of an assessment of the impact of various principles on her life as a whole, how to prioritize various practical principles. When the time comes for action, which practical principles are living and which are dead will be determined by this prioritization. One who lacks character might similarly establish a ranking of practical principles (resolving, for instance, to prioritize getting an early start on one’s day over satisfying the inclination to rest by sleeping in), but the inclinations of the moment, rather than this resolution, will determine which practical principle becomes the basis for choice.

           

            The final added component of Kant's account is by far the most important. Kant thinks that human beings are capable not only of “impure” principles of action that are ““intellectual . . . in some respect,” but also of purely intellectual principles of action. In particular, human beings have a “predisposition to the good” (xxx), a “moral predisposition” (xxx) that gives rise to a principle that is “purely intellectual without qualification” because it is an “impelling cause” that “is represented by the pure understanding” (28:589). A purely intellectual principle is not based in any way on one’s instincts or inclinations but proceeds solely from practical reason itself. In chapter three, we saw the importance from the standpoint of transcendental anthropology (moral philosophy) of the possibility of an “autonomous” moral law, a principle governing human actions that does not require appeal to inclination for its justification. Within Kant's psychology, the nature of pure practical principles is somewhat different, as a principle of the higher faculty of desire that does not require positing any particular instincts or inclinations as factors in its explanation.

In chapter three, however, we noted that Kant's account of the free finitude of human beings requires some account of how the moral law can motivate human beings that are objects of empirical description. Kant's empirical anthropology in general provides the basic biological-psychological background for such an account. Like other basic powers/predispositions, the predisposition to the good can simply be posited in human nature. Like instincts, Kant suggests that this predisposition is innate in human beings: “xxx” (xxx, cf. xxx). But like all predispositions of the faculty of desire (including instincts), other experiential factors determine the extent to which the moral predisposition is living and efficacious or amounts to a mere wish. Thus Kant points out that xxx quote re: causing good, e.g. of moral education, politeness, moral community in religion.

From the standpoint of the environmental and predispositional bases of moral motivation, Kant's account of moral motivation thus fits well into his general empirical anthropology. Because of the importance of moral motivation for his transcendental anthropology, however, and especially the importance of making sense of how a finite, empirically situated being can be motivated by a pure moral law, Kant adds detailed specific accounts of the nature of the “feeling of respect” that serves as the anticipatory “pleasure” causing choice in accordance with the moral law.

Kant's account of respect for the moral law is notoriously difficult to interpret. On the one hand, Kant says that “no feeling” (xx). But only a paragraph later, he describes “feeling xxx.” Understandably, readers of Kant are largely split into those that favor a “cognitivist” reading and those that favor a “sentimentalist” xxx.

Given that Kant posits both a transcendental and an empirical anthropology, of course, it is understandable that he might give different accounts of the role of pleasure in moral motivation. From the inside-out standpoint of transcendental anthropology, pleasure cannot play any role in grounding decisions to act in accordance with the moral law. If I choose to do what is right because it is (or will be) pleasurable, I do not choose autonomously, and hence do not really choose to do what is right. Xxx

Theoretically, then, there is no reason that Kant cannot insist upon the absence of pleasure as a motive from the standpoint of practical deliberation while incorporating moral motivation into his more general empirical psychology such that the thought of the pure moral principle gives rise to a desire and thereby an action by means of pleasure. In his lectures on empirical psychology, Kant even talks about an “intellectual pleasure” xxx. And much of Kant's account of respect seems to fit with this general account: xxx, xxx.

But Kant also worries about subsuming his account of moral motivation too closely withunder his account of motivation in general. Part of the reason for this may be concerns about the way in which transcendental and empirical anthropology relate. It can just seem odd to say that one is motivated by a purely moral principle but only by means of a pleasure one takes in it, and even if one reserves this for the level of empirical explanation, it can seem to make moral motivation too hedonistic. But part of the reason also seems to be strictly empirical. Whereas ordinary desires for objects seem to motivate by means of pleasure, and one can even see impure practical principles as motivating in this way, the moral law just seems to motivate more directly, without bringing any pleasure in any traditional sense. Thus Kant suggests that “xxx not a real feeling just a moving aside”.

 

xxxKant's response to the first problem involves an account of “in what way the moral law becomes an incentive and, inasmuch as it is, what happens to the human faculty of desire as an effect of that determining ground upon it” (5:72). In other words, insofar as the moral law determines one’s free choice, what are the effects of this determination on the empirically observable faculty of desire? Kant's short answer is that motivation by the moral law appears in an agent’s empirical psychology as feeling of “respect” for the moral law (4: xxx, 5: 72f.). A full explanation

 

respect is “nothing other than the sensation of the determinability of the will through reason itself, thus not a special feeling and distinctive receptivity that requires a special section under the properties of the mind” (20:207)

 

 

 

6) Conclusion

 

            Insofar as they are objects of empirical study, human beings are biological beings with complex mental lives. As biological beings, we have various predispositions that are best discussed in terms of the ends that they serve, and these predispositions provide the grounds for the causal laws that determine how our environment shapes our cognitions, feelings, and desires. Xxx We are unique among biological beings in having higher faculties of cognition (true?) and in being historical xxx.

            Even in terms of empirical psychology, Kant made important contributions to the empirical account of human beings. Vs. Wolff re: one-faculty.  Vs. Hume re: reason xxx. (Build more of this back in xxx)

 

 

 

 

 

 

 



[1] There are four key aspects of Kant’s empirical account of the human being. First, as we saw in chapter two, one crucial issue in the development of empirical psychology in the second half of the 18th century was the structure of the human mind. Whereas Wolff had sought to reduce all human mental states to the single category of “representation” and all capacities to a single “xxx capacity for representation,” there was an increasing sense that this reduction obscured essential differences between, for example, volition and cognition. In this context, Kant developed his own elaborate faculty psychology, defending a three-fold set of faculties each of which could be further subdivided into irreducibly distinct mental powers. Second, Kant overlaid onto his discussion of human mental powers an account of various causal laws that govern those powers and their relations. For Kant, “the concept of cause lies in the concept of power” (28:564),[1] so the elucidation of different mental powers provides the framework for a discussion of the causal laws that govern those powers. Third, Kant entered into 18th century debates within biology and embryology about the extent to which various human (mental) tendencies and capacities are innate or acquired. In that context, Kant developed an account of the human being rooted in the presence of various “germs” (Keime) and “predispositions” (Anlagen) that could be cultivated in different ways depending on human’s context. The way in which these germs and predispositions develop determines, in large part, the way in which human mental powers operate. Fourth, this account of predispositions (and germs) provided a background for an account of human history and human differences. In that context, Kant entered into a growing interest within the 18th century in thinking of the human being as a fundamentally historical being . Herder, one of Kant’s students and an eventual philosophical rival, explained that “xxx.” And Kant himself pointed out that “xxxhuman progress as a species and in history xxx.”

 

[2]  Throughout this paper, reference to Kant are to the Academy Edition of Kant’s works or to the standard A and B editions of the Critique of Pure Reason.  For English translations, I have made extensive use of the Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant, where available, and of translations of the Anthropology by Victor Lyle Dowdell (Southern Illinois University Press: 1978), Mary Gregor (Martinus Nijhoff: 1974), and Robert Louden (Cambridge University Press: forthcoming).

[3] In a lecture on metaphysics, Kant reiterates this, making clear that “nature” here refers not simply to the realm of outer sense – bodies – but to inner sense – the mind – as well: “All things in nature, be they inner or outer events, have their determining cause, they all happen according to natural laws and are also determined according to them” (28:582).  Working out the precise relationship between inner and outer events is beyond the scope of this paper, although it would have important implications for the extent to which Kant allows reductionism with respect to mental events.  For my purposes, I focus on showing Kant has a causal account of mental events.  Whether this is in principle reducible to a physical account is beyond the scope of this paper.

[4] Cf. Allison.

[5] Cf. Reath, Baron.

[6] Cf. wood, louden.

[7] In the Critique of Judgment, Kant even explicitly distinguishes these two kinds of universality: “Here it is understood that the universality [Allgemeinheit] is only comparative, so that the rules are only general [generale] (as all empirical rules are), not universal [universale]” (5: 213).  Allgemein is the term generally translated “universal” in Kant’s writings, and in particular is the term used to describe the “universality” of radical evil in the Religion (6: 29).  In the Anthropology as well, Kant is careful to use Generalkenntnis to describe the “universal” knowledge involved in anthropology (7:120).  In both cases, the knowledge at issue is universal only in the comparative sense.  As Kant insists concerning radical evil (which we will discuss in detail in the next chapter), “there is no cause for exempting anyone from it” (6:25), but this universality is merely contingent (6:29).

[8] Cf. Wood 1999: 198.

[9] E.g. Gouax 1972, Westphal xxx.

[10] See Frierson xxx, Hatfield (1990, 1992), and Sturm (2001) for more defense xxx.

[11] Quote goes on:

“Strictly speaking, human beings are sooner worth the effort to be studied, and that they are given their due by such considerations, than the entire physical nature. One believed there to be too little to be said about this in a science; hence one inserted it into metaphy­sics, and in fact into psychology, which constitutes empirical psychology, where it does not belong at all, in that metaphysics has nothing to do with any empirical sciences.”

[12]

As Marcia Baron puts it, “

She goes on:

This [causal picture of agency] is a familiar picture of agency from the empiricist tradition. Kant’s theory of agency is very different.  Our actions are not the result of a desire or some other incentive that impels us.  An incentive can move us to act only if we let it. (Baron 1995: 189)

 

[13] Cf. too Baron 1995:189, Westphal 357-8, and even Wood (2003: 50).

[14]  Footnote re: the sense in which empiricists buy incorporation thesis (e.g. Locke on reflective distance) and Hume on calm passions xxx.

[15] As we will see, there are important differences between Kant’s empirical psychology and standard empiricist accounts, and some of these differences make Kant’s empirical psychology particularly well suited to fit with his transcendental accounts of freedom, but Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason provides a framework for reconciling transcendental freedom with any empirical description of human actions.  For further discussion of this claim, see Frierson (under review).

[16] Footnote on evaluation . . . note that evaluation is a kind of sympathetic deliberation xxx.

[17] . Sometimes this variation in behavior is involuntary; often it is voluntary. Human beings are particularly adept at deception and dissembling (cf. 25:857-9, 25:1197). And even with respect to self-observation, Kant points out that human beings are adept at self-deception and not particularly attuned to incentives that might prove unflattering (G xxx, Rel xxx, Anth 7:133).

[18] . When one is overcome with anger, for example, it is impossible to actually observe the nature of that anger because anger prevents the calm interest and introspective attention involved in self-study . And when the anger has passed, one can no longer see – and cannot accurately remember – what the anger looks like in action.

[19]

In addition to these epistemic challenges with knowledge of human beings, Kant suggests that introspection can actually have dangerous effects on one’s psychological health, so that even if one could gather the relevant data, it might not be worth the cost.   (25:252, 477-8, 863-5, xxx).

[20] Kant also includes such authors as Samuel Richardson, Moliere, the English Spectator (by Allison and Steele), xxx. For references to literature as a source of anthropology, see 7: 221, 25:473, Add refs and more literature.

[21]  For more discussion, cf. Frierson 2003: xxx.

[22] Cf too

“philosophers who otherwise deserve nothing but praise . . . have sought to explain this distinction as merely illusory and to reduce all faculties to the mere faculty of cognition. But it can easily be demonstrated . . . that this attempt to bring unity into the multiplicity of faculties, although undertake in a genuinely philosophical spirit, is futile. For there is always a great difference between representations belonging to cognition, insofar as they are related merely to the object and the unity of the consciousness of it, and their objective relation where, considered as at the same time the cause of the relatiy of this object, they are assigned to the faculty of desire, and, finally, their relation merely to the subject, where theyare considered merely as grounds for preserving their own existence in it and to this extent in relation to the feeling of pleasure; the latter is absolutely not a cognition, nor does it provide one, althoguht ot be sure it may presuppose such a cognition as a determining ground” (20:206, KU, 1st intro).

[23] Cf. Crusius 1745, §§ 73 and 444; Watkins 2005: 91; Hatfield 1990.

[24]  In some cases, Kant associates the spontaneity of the higher faculty with that transcendental freedom that is a condition of possibility of moral responsibility, but in his empirical psychology, Kant generally uses the terms “self-activity” or “spontaneity” to describe an empirical or comparative freedom of the higher faculties, a freedom that is consistent with the view that even those higher faculties are causally determined. Strictly speaking, describing the higher faculty of desire as free in that sense is inconsistent with empirical psychology.  Insofar as one studies human action empirically, such action is, as Kant insists in his first Critique, causally necessitated in accordance with natural laws.  But Kant does hold that the presence of a higher faculty of desire is an indication of moral responsibility and hence transcendental freedom.  (See Frierson, “Kant’s Empirical Account of Human Action” and “Kant’s Empirical Markers of Moral Responsibility”)  Thus he sometimes slips into these properly transcendental discussions in lectures on empirical psychology.  This effort to discuss the Critical philosophy in lectures on empirical psychology is not particularly surprising, of course.  As a teacher, Kant found an opportunity within the syllabus prescribed by Baumgarten’s text for explaining some of Kant’s own more important philosophical ideas, a temptation to which he can hardly be blamed for succumbing.

[25] Cf. e.g. 7:196, where Kant explains the differences between these faculties, and related sections of lectures in empirical psychology (28:73-5, 242-3, 863-5; 29: 888-90) and anthropology (25: 537, 773-4, 1032f., 1296, 1476).  Kant’s placement of the power of judgment (Urteilskraft) in the higher cognitive faculty is a notable departure from Baumgarten, who places it in the lower cognitive faculty (see Metaphysica §§ 606-9).  A detailed comparison of Baumgarten and Kant on the nature of judgment would reward further study but is beyond the scope of the present paper.

[26] Here I focus on Kant’s account of the higher and lower faculties of desire, as these are tied to action most directly, but most of Kant’s account of higher and lower desire applies to feeling as well, although, as already noted, Kant’s account of the difference between higher and lower faculties of feeling is complicated by his efforts to distinguish between intellectual and sensible feelings for moral purposes. 

[27] Kant makes the same claim in the context of pleasure, but there Kant is careful to insist that while there is still a lower and higher faculty of pleasure, all pleasure is sensitive in itself (hence lower). 

[28] Here again (recall footnote 50)., Kant leaves open the metaphysical possibility that “the unity of each substance requires that there be only one basic power” (29:822). 

[29] Xxx revise footnote (or just cut it?)( xxx from British empiricism Kant adopted the practice of explaining each power in terms of laws describing regular connections between phenomena. Unlike many of the British empiricists, Kant does not focus on laying out causal laws and applying them to understand various mental phenomena. Kant’s focus is on the framework of basic powers that will ground those causal laws. And Kant allows a greater plurality of basic powers than most empiricists.  Moreover, because these laws are rooted in basic powers, they reflect necessary connections between different phenomenal states, rather than mere regularities. Most importantly, Kant differs from empiricists in that he does not think that an empirical account of basic powers provides any basis for epistemology or ethics.  In his Critique of Pure Reason, Kant insists that although “as far as time is concerned . . ., every cognition begins with experience,” nonetheless “it does not all on that account arise from experience” (B 1-2, cf. 29: 951-2).  In a similar way, Kant argues that his empirical account of human action does not imply that ethical norms can be derived from this account.  But when Kant does describe the laws governing the basic powers, his laws are similar to those of the empiricists, including a “law of association” governing the imagination and various laws of logic and prejudice governing the understanding.

[30] This account of human action is identical for animal action.  Like humans, other animals have cognitions, feelings, and desires.  Kant even describes animals as having “choice [Willkühr]” (cf. 6:213, 28:588, 29:1015).  The difference between humans and animals is that humans have a “higher” faculty of cognition, and hence of desire, and this gives humans a kind of empirical freedom than animals lack.  This shows that at least Kant’s general picture of human action does not imply any transcendental freedom.  Kant nowhere suggests that animals have transcendental freedom, so insofar as they are motivated by similar structures as human beings, there is nothing “free” about these structures in themselves.

[31] Xxx Include any of this in text (or note)???::

Insofar as a representation is the ground of an action that brings about some state of affairs, it is a desire: “the faculty of the soul for becoming cause of the actuality of the object through the representation of the object itself = . . . the faculty of desire” (29:1012, cf. 6: 211, 399; 7:251).  An “object” here is not necessarily a physical object but anything that can be desired, including physical objects but also states of affairs.[31] The object of desire is a possible purpose for an action, and desires, for Kant, naturally give rise to actions.  As Kant puts it here, a desire is defined as a representation that leads to action, that “becomes cause of the actuality of an object.”[31]  And when desire is taken in this sense, there are no actions that are not preceded by and caused by desires, and no desires that do not lead to actions (at least in the absence of external impediments).[31]

[32] Xxx edit xxx add ref to conflicts of desires xxx Because desires simply are representations insofar as those representations are directed towards action, Kant’s notion of desire is more closely connected to choice and action than the customary English sense of desire, whereby one can desire something without actually pursuing it.  Once one has a desire in this general sense, one is committed to action, and action follows necessarily in the absence of unforeseen hindrances.  One might, for example, desire a mango and then find oneself unable to climb the tree, but one’s representation will not count as a desire unless it prompts one to action.  In contrast to customary English usage, for Kant desires mark an end to deliberation, not factors taken into account in deliberation.

 

Cf. 20:230n re: wishes.xxx

[33] Xxx Cut and revise this stuff to make this a good footnote just about the problematic issue of pleasure always preceding desire, and action always flowing from desire. Xxxx

Similarly, the connection between feeling and desire is, for Kant, a very close one.  In his empirical psychology, Kant usually emphasizes this tight connection between feeling and desire, pointing out that “the cognitive faculty is connected with the faculty of desire by the feeling of pleasure or displeasure” (29:890) or that the feeling of “satisfaction with the actuality of the object is desire” (25:577; cf. 7:230-1, 25: 1514).[33]  He insists,

The faculty of desire rests on the principle: I desire nothing but what pleases, and avoid nothing but what displeases . . . . But representations cannot be the cause of an object where we have no pleasure or displeasure in it.  This is therefore the subjective condition by which alone a representation can become the cause of an object.  (29:894)[33]

In these lectures, the cognition–feeling–desire model of motivation seems to be universal, and Kant even applies this model explicitly to the case of motivation by reason.  He explains,

[F]reedom is the faculty for choosing that which is good in itself and not merely good as a means.  Thus we are free when we arrange out actions entirely according to the laws of the understanding and of reason, and the more we do this, the freer we are, for even if the will is free from stimuli, it can still be not entirely free.  For since we desire merely that which pleases us, pleasure is the cause of our desiring.  But the cause of the pleasure is either sensibility or understanding . . . .  Understanding and reason give laws to the will according to which it must conform if it is to be free.  But we cannot be determined by mere representations of reason; it must also give us incentives. (29:899-900; cf. 19:185-6, R6866; 28:253-4).

Here Kant holds firm to his cognition–pleasure–desire model, pointing out only that there are two very different kinds of pleasure, depending upon whether those pleasures are caused by sensible or intellectual cognitions.  Elsewhere Kant makes a similar point, and he develops a vocabulary for distinguishing between the general genus of feeling that is a cause of any sort of desire and the narrower sort of feeling that is purely sensible:

The cognitive faculty is connected with the faculty of desire by the feeling of pleasure or displeasure. The author calls it pleasure <voluptas> and dipleasure <taedium>.  That is false, for this is true only of sensible satisfaction.  – For the understanding can frequently find dissatisfaction with that which best satisfies the senses.  This should be named the faculty of satisfaction and dissatisfaction.” (29:890, cf. 28:674-5, 29:1013)

In the context of his empirical psychology, Kant generally posits a feeling of satisfaction [Wohlgefallen] or dissatisfaction [Mißgefallen] as a cause of any desire, allowing that these feelings can be either caused by sensibility (in which case they are properly called pleasures [Lust] or displeasures [Unlust]) or by the understanding.

                In the context of his moral philosophy, however, Kant sometimes suggests that no feeling of any sort precedes purely moral volitions.  Some of the strongest language here is from the second Critique, where Kant says, 

What is essential to any moral worth of actions is that the moral law determine the will immediately.  If the determination of the will takes place conformably with the law but only by means of a feeling, of whatever kind, that has to be presupposed in order for the law to become a sufficient determining ground of the will, so that the action is not done for the sake of the law, then the action will contain legality indeed but not morality.  (5:71-2, cf. 4:401n, 5:9n, 6:212, 29:1024)

One way to read this passage is as an exception to Kant’s cognition–feeling–desire model of motivation.  On this reading, feelings would precede desires only for the cases of non-moral motivation.  In the case of motivation by the moral law, the relevant feelings would follow the determination of one’s faculty of desire. 

A full discussion of these passages would require a detailed treatment of the feeling of respect for the moral law, which is beyond the scope of the present essay.[33]  However, it is worth noting that there is another way to read these passages, one that is consistent with Kant’s general model of human motivation.  The key to reconciling this passage with Kant’s general cognition–feeling–desire model of motivation is to focus on the claim that feeling cannot play a role as an antecedent “determining ground of the will,”[33] and to read this restriction as one that applies not to empirical descriptions of choice, but to one’s deliberative bases for choice.  That is, in the case of motivation by the moral law, one does not appeal to pleasure as a determining ground of one’s choice, but simply to the law as such.  In non-moral motivation, one appeals in deliberation, either directly or indirectly, to the pleasure that one takes in the object of one’s choice.  In moral motivation, one makes no such appeal to pleasure.  This would be compatible, of course, with saying that pleasure plays a role in a psychological account of choice, as a connecting psychological state between cognition of the moral law and one’s desire.  Here the thought of the moral law in all its purity (hence not mixed with any considerations of pleasure) causes a pleasure that brings about the desire to act in accordance with the moral law.  Kant makes a similar point elsewhere, arguing,

One must never say that one places one’s end in gratification, rather that whatever immediately gratifies us is our end, because gratification is only the relation of an end to our feeling.  The satisfaction in the rule-governedness of freedom is intellectual.  Hence the end is not always self-seeking, if the end is not the altered condition of our own senses. (19:190-1, R6881)

In the case of respect for the moral law, no antecedent gratification determines one’s ends in action, and thus one’s action is not self-seeking, but the immediate interest taken in the moral law itself is a kind of gratification, which in turn motivates desire and thereby action.

For the purpose of this paper, I take the cognition-feeling-desire model of motivation to be Kant’s most consistent model, even for higher cognitions.  Those cases in which Kant claims that intellectual feelings merely follow upon desire/choice, rather than grounding it, can be read as presenting a practical account of motivation.  Even in the case of higher (intellectual) desires, one’s higher cognitions have “impelling causes” that are feelings of “satisfaction of dissatisfaction,” but these are not “pleasures” strictly speaking because they do not “depend on the manner in which we are [sensibly] affected by objects” (28:254, cf. 29:895). These feelings of satisfaction (or even pleasure) do not provide reasons (in the first personal sense of reasons that one should consider in deliberation) for one’s actions, though they can still be present as empirical causes that connect one’s intellectual cognitions with desires.[33]  At the empirical level, then, the cognition–feeling–desire model of motivation works even for intellectual feelings, though these are feelings of satisfaction rather than pleasure.[33]

                Within this picture, feelings of satisfaction and dissatisfaction function as transitions from cognitions to desires (and thereby to actions).  Jeanine Grenberg has described the connection between these “practical pleasures” and desire in detail (Grenberg 2001: 160-3).[33]  As she explains,

[P]ractical pleasure is itself necessarily related to and is indeed the very vehicle for the expression of the status of an agent’s faculty of desire.  Technically . . . there is a distinction to be made between feeling and desire: feeling, an element of the agent’s sensible nature . . . “determines” (bestimmt) the faculty of desire . . ..  For the purposes of describing action, there is, however, little distinction to be made between the possession of a practical pleasure and that of a desire.  (Grenberg 2001: 163)[33]

In the rest of this paper, I follow Grenberg in downplaying the distinction between pleasure and desire.  Given a practical pleasure, a desire will follow simply because of the nature of practical pleasures.  The challenge for giving a causal account of human action is to explain the origin of those practical pleasures/desires.

                Given the close connections between feeling, desire, and action, this paper focuses on giving a causal account of human action in terms of the connections between cognitions and desires.  Throughout, these connections are mediated by feelings of satisfaction and dissatisfaction.  And these desires all reflect a subjective commitment to action in a particular case.  These desires lead to action except in cases of further (and not fundamentally psychological) interference, as when a sudden accident or unforeseen complication prevents one from following through on one’s volitional commitment.  Thus outlining how cognitions cause desires reflects the most important psychological component of a causal account of human action.  This task is complicated, however, because not all cognitions lead to desire or aversion.  Even within those cognitions that do affect desire, some lead to desire and others lead to aversion.  Thus Kant needs some account of why the series goes through in some cases and not others, and why it leads to the conative state that it does.  In order to provide the framework for Kant’s account of how cognitions effect desires, the rest of this section lays out requisite details from Kant’s faculty psychology.  In the next several sections (three through five), I explain the role of predispositions as causal bases of connections between specific cognitions and desires. 

[34]  Cf. e.g. Locke xxx, Hume xxx.

[35] It is important to distinguish the role of analogy as a principle of imagination and a principle of judgment.  In the imagination, “empirical ideas that have frequently followed one another produce a habit in the mind such that when one idea is produced, the other also comes into being” (7: 176).  Here the transition from one idea to the next is immediate.  In the case of the faculty of judgment, the cognition of a particular judgment (that two things are similar in many respects) gives rise to a further judgment (that they are similar in other respects) by means of an implicit principle of judging.

[36] My account of deviations from proper functioning of the higher cognitive faculties here focused on those deviations that take place in ordinary human knowers. Kant's account of mental illness will be discussed in chapter six.

[37] When discussing the “higher” faculty of desire (see below), Kant sometimes suggests that pleasure does not precede desire.  Some of the strongest language here is from the second Critique, where Kant says, 

What is essential to any moral worth of actions is that the moral law determine the will immediately.  If the determination of the will takes place conformably with the law but only by means of a feeling, of whatever kind, that has to be presupposed in order for the law to become a sufficient determining ground of the will, so that the action is not done for the sake of the law, then the action will contain legality indeed but not morality.  (5:71-2)

This passage could be read merely to refer to first personal grounds of choice rather than to empirical causes of choice, but it might also be read psychologically.  The former interpretation, which fits better with the account of pleasure offered in this paper, is supported in part by Kant’s appeal later in this discussion to a “positive feeling” of “respect for the moral law” (5:73), a “moral feeling . . . produced solely by reason” that serves “as an incentive to make this [moral] law its [the will’s] maxim” (5:76).  For detailed studies of these passages, see Allison 1989, McCarty 1993 and 1994, and Reath 1989. A similar tension between an intellectual feeling that causes choice and an insistence that feeling must play no role occurs throughout Kant’s lectures and other writings.  Thus in the Metaphysics of Morals, Kant distinguishes between an “interest of inclination” where “a pleasure necessarily precedes a desire” and an “intellectual pleasure” that “can only follow upon an antecedent determination of the faculty of desire” (6:212, cf. 29:1024). 

But in a lecture of the same period  (1794-5), Kant deals with the issue of pleasure differently.  He first distinguishes between “pleasure” (Lust) and “satisfaction” (Wohlgefallen), the latter of which is “more general” (29:1013) and includes both intellectual and sensible satisfaction.  (In this context, “pleasure” describes the subset of satisfaction that is purely sensible.)  But Kant then claims that “desiring” has its “ground” in “satisfaction with respect to the actuality of the object” (29:1013).  (Even in that set of lectures, however, Kant distinguishes between the higher and lower faculties of desire by saying that the “impelling causes” of an action “lie either in the understanding as the law of action [in which case the cause is a higher desire], or in the sensibility, namely, in the feeling of pleasure and displeasure,” in which latter case the cause is a lower desire (29:1014).  Here Kant seems to conflate sensibility with feeling and to associate both exclusively with the lower faculty of desire.)

 

[38] “faculty for determining oneself from an inner principle according to the power of choice” (28:275)

Shared by animals (28:275f.)

[39] xxx quote continues “We can name in a threefold manner the objects of the feeling of pleasure and displeasure.”

[40]  For the sake of simplicity, I here ignore the important distinction between the feeling of pleasure at the agreeable and at the good. xxx

[41] This discussion taken from Sloan 2002. See Sloan for more details. Sloan thinks that Kant abandoned even his modified preformationism (and thus the centrality of the notion of Anlagen) after reading Blumenbach in 1790. I do not agree with this conclusion xxx.

[42]  Strictly speaking, Descartes did not extend his account to human mental life, but xxx.

[43] Strictly speaking, this is Kant's overall definition of both germs and predispositions. The relationship between Anlage and Keime is ambiguous and seems to shift over time in Kant. For discussion, see Sloan, Munzel xxx. For the purpose of the account offered here, I treat Keime and Anlage as equivalent, as Kant sometimes seems to do (for example, xxxlater race essay? xxx).

[44]  Kant says “evolution” here, but “evolution” is a standard 18th century term for preformationism.

[45]  To get from the epistemic sense of preformationism to this reliance on natural purposes requires some account of why purposiveness should be seen to be present in natural organisms. This missing premise was discussed in chapter three. xxx

[46]  In his lectures on metaphysics, Kant even takes this sort of teleological explanation of natural predispositions as an argument for the immortality of the soul, since many human natural predispositions do not have a this-worldly purpose (see 29:915).

[47]  Keefe: Is this the best place to put this ¶, or should it go somewhere else?

[48] Discuss whether/why powers are strictly necessary (cf. issues in Kistler & Gnassounou, eds, 2007).

[49]  Strictly speaking, the picture here is more complicated. Insert from paper. Also note productive vs. reproduction and complications related to that. Reference paper for more.

[50] In this essay, Kant emphasizes the cooperation between imagination and reason in the extension of one’s natural instincts and inclinations.  However, one can also conceive of an extension that is purely due to imagination, as I suggest here.

[51] xxx Reath, etc ; perhaps also Blackburn? xxx

[52]  Within his moral philosophy, when Kant refers to “inclinations,” this term includes instincts as well.

[53]  Somewhere in this section, add a footnote re: passions. Xxx Discuss in more detail in chapter 7.

[54] The latter passages, from Kant's lectures, make clear that Kant does not see this propensity to intoxicants as unique to “savages” but rather as a general human propensity that affects even savages.

[55] For more on the importance of character for Kant’s moral philosophy, see Munzel 1999 and Kuehn 2001.

[56] (25:208-10, 411, 474)

[57] ; cf.25:227, another ref at cf. Kuehn 2001:147

[58]

Kant makes the nature of this connection clearer elsewhere, explaining that “the essential characteristic of character . . . belongs to the firmness of the principles” (25:1175, cf. 25:630, 651-52, 1384).  A person whose actions are explained by reference to their “character” is someone whose faculty of desire is determined by principles flowing from the higher cognitive faculties. The relevant principles here need not specifically be moral; any principles can be practical in that they guide action.  As Kant makes clear in his Anthropology, acting on the basis of firm principles, regardless of the content of those principles, determines whether or not someone has character:

Simply to have a character relates to that property of the will by which the subject has tied himself to certain practical principles . . .. Although these principles may sometimes indeed be false or defective, nevertheless the formal element of will as such, which is determined to act according to firm principles (not shifting hither and yon like a swarm of gnats), has something precious and admirable to it, which is also something rare. (7:292, cf. 25:651-52)

A person who acts from any stable set of principles has character. [58] 

[59]  It is important here to distinguish between maxims as first-personal reasons for action and maxims as parituclar mental states that cause action xxx.

[60] Unlike the case of lower desires, where the “principle” of one’s action is something of which one is not conscious, a mere disposition to act in a particular way, higher desires involve circumstances actually prompting cognition of a relevant principle.

[61] (In this respect, Kant's account of “character” is grossly at odds with the use of “character” in neo-Aristotelian “virtue ethics.”)

[62] For more on the role of politeness in cultivating character, see Brender 1997, 1998, and Frierson 2005.

[63] In general, in fact, human desires flow from principles to which we are committed in order to satisfy the instincts and inclinations of our lower faculty of desire. Sometimes these connections will be straightforward: human beings in wealthy nations typically consume food not immediately from instinct but from principles according to which we recognize the eating of food to be both immediately worthy of pursuit (because pleasurable) and ultimately useful for providing nourishment. Even foolish consumption of junk food is generally not directly instinctual but is a deliberate effort to satisfy the cravings of instinct according to principles – “Snickers really satisfies” – that we incorporate into the character of our higher faculty of desire.


 [u1] Cut to no more than 11,000 words.

 [KP2]You might explicitly point out the contrast with the common thought that one’s inner self can be known as it is in itself and is not subject to causal laws.  (I see now that you sort of do this below.  It might be good to even contrast Kant with another author, like Descartes).  

 [j3]Will the reader know that for Kant the fact that we nonetheless blame the agent implies that the agent is free?  Might they take this quote simply that Kant is very hard and unfair?

 [j4]Maybe note, Kant follows Hume in this regard (but only from the empirical perspective). 

 [KP5]All of the other three reasons are philosophical reasons, whereas this is purely an interpretive reason.  Can you present this instead in terms of the philosophical reasons against the possibility of an empirical human science?

 [u6] Switch first and second xxx. Add footnote in MFNS discussion with specific reasons and also dealing with Westphal.

 [KP7]If you end up needing to shorten this chapter, you could probably condense this discussion of universality to just a couple of sentences.  Throughout this section, you spend a lot of time setting up the apparent problems.  This makes it exciting when they are resolved, but sometimes they don’t require as much attention as you give them. 

 [u8] Connect with KU discussion from chapter 3. (This relates to next comment.)

 [KP9]You’ve shown why Kant’s statements about universality don’t preclude the possibility of making comparative universal claims based on experience, but I don’t think you’ve done much to show why we can in fact claim that something holds without exception based on experience. 

 [KP10]How does it appear when one excludes all inclinations from consideration out of respect for the moral law?  It seems like if the incorporation thesis is true, the empirical explanation of our actions is just false or meaningless. 

 [u11] Insert example of angel transcendentally freely grounding gravity, but we still study it as though it’s merely empirical.

 [KP12]It might be fun to use a good quote from Montaigne or Shakespeare about human nature.  Do Montaigne and Shakespeare really tell us things that are true of all human beings?  What does this look like?  Will you include these kinds of things in the book.  This reminds me, often when I tell someone that the book is about human  nature these are some of the things they think it will be about:

Whether humans are inherently good or evil, why humans love to complain to each other, why humans always talk about things like the weather with strangers...

The first one is obviously included in this book, but the second and third don’t seem like the kind of thing included in this book. 

 [u13] Look for quotes from literature and then cool Kantian generalizations from them…perhaps Tristam Shandy re: drink – deliberate—sober up—decide.  In any case, give specific examples of Kant's use of literature.

 [KP14] Given this argument, why does it even make sense to subsume them under a common title?

à Add a couple sentences distinguishing common “titles” (e.g. Kant himself uses “representation” generically, but also subsumes powers under cognitive, feeling, desire, etc.) and different basic powers.

 

“Difference between common characteristics of different powers, and a common power that operates differently in different circumstances.”

 

Perhaps insert the “if it doesn’t move by degrees from one to the other, then it’s not a common power” quote to explain difference.

 

Think of why we can reduce red and yellow perception to one power, but not red and loud.

 [KP15]What does it mean that these “only become articulated as such”?

EXPLAIN WHAT THIS MEANS…IN PARTICULAR, THAT WE NECESSARILY IMPOSE THE categories of causation on the world and thus the world necessarily appears to us as causal, but we don’t necessarily formulate the concept “causation” until after extended reflection, abstraction, etc.  (Little kids understand causation, but not the words “cause” and “effect.”)

 

Difference is difference between forming a comparatively universal concept and a strictly universal one . . . hence the nature of the reflection has to be different, less like induction.  In empirical concepts, we reflect on what we find to be common between associated representations; in a priori ones, we reflect on what we find ourselves to assume/project onto associated representations.  We may not be conscious of this difference, but it’s there, hence the a priori ones arise from the understanding according to its nature…what we are really reflecting on is the operation of the understanding, even though it seems as though we are reflecting on objects/events.

 

Highlight how “association” here invokes the imagination.

 

Distinguish original concept formation and later…later we can use concepts to look for more (i.e. ask whether all green things have something more in common, etc).  For first concepts, imagination may need to provide the initial bundle/comparison class through its own (non-conceptual) principles of association.  Draw from krv for more on this….be sure to make this empirical and distinguish from transcendental aspect of krv.

 

Look at how Kant actually tries to give his readers an idea of causation in KrV (i.e., “causes always precede, etc…”).

 [KP16]Does this necessarily link it with desire?  When one takes pleasure in the beautiful isn’t one indifferent to whether the state persists or not?

MAYBE DEALT WITH LATER?  BE SURE.

 [KP17]Isn’t want a synonym for desire?

MAYBE DEALT WITH LATER?  BE SURE.

 [KP18]This is a really interesting definition.  I am reminded of the painful frustration of having to work in a room where the ceiling is shorter than my height, or of the pleasure of my vision being cleared or of stepping out of a car.  But this only seems to capture one type of pleasure or displeasure.  How does the pain of getting punched relate to the hindrance of some activity?  We avoid getting battered in general so that we can stay healthy and active, but in many particular cases the pain occurs without any relation to the promotion of life or activity.  The pain then is not always a result of the consciousness of the advancement of one’s powers, nor is it always the result of an actual advancement of one’s powers, but is rather the result of some phenomenon that tends to advance one’s powers or that one consciously recognizes to advance one’s powers. 

 

PERHAPS PUT IN SHELL STUFF HERE?

 

Teleological account help here?  But this is the definition/essence of pain.

 [u19]Finish this.

 [KP20]But it is not one’s mental state that is conducive to life, it is one’s objective state.

THINK ABOUT SOME MORE.

 [KP21]This distinction is very helpful.  It resolves my earlier problem. 

 [KP22]Nice clear summarizing sentence. 

 [KP23]Not necessarily physical.  One could will to think about something. 

 [u24] Take it out.

 [KP25]This clears up the trouble I had with the last draft.   

 [KP26]Obviously it is tough to capture in a single phrase, but this doesn’t give me a very good idea of Buffon’s take on epigenesis.

ADD SUMMARY SENTENCE/REPHRASE.

 [KP27]Does Kant give an argument for why chance could not have produced such agreements? 

 

ADD A “BECAUSE” CLAUSE.

 [u28] Rephrase: “but even if we can give causal relations between physical and mental events and even provide accounts of the material conditions for various mental powers, . . .”

 [KP29]Is this a good objection? Can’t one know mental phenomenal by having it described by one who perceives it through the inner sense?  Can’t we investigate causal relationships in the same way we do between material objects, by observing one phenomena repeatedly following another?

 

PERHAPS LINK TO CONTEMPORARY ACCOUNTS IN PHILOSOPHY OF MIND (QUALIA, ETC).

 

Perhaps explain reductionism a bit more, for those who don’t know what reductionism is.

 

“DIFFERENT IN KIND EVEN IF NUMERICALLY IDENTICAL”

 [KP30]This is a very clear and useful model. 

 [KP31]Odd transition.  This is a completely new idea, not the continuation of a theme. 

 [KP32]It seems clear that both practical pleasures arise in this case. 

ACTUALLY CF. Kant's ACCOUNT OF RESPECT WHERE THE FRUSTRATION OF INCLINATION CAUSES PAIN, SO MAYBE THE ONE WE DON’T ACT ON LEADS TO US FEELING PAIN.

 

Somewhere perhaps add fn re: that underlying grounds might even affect the extent to which anticipatory pleasures give rise to desires. Eg. Inclinations might be able to give rise to anticipatory pleasures but not real desires if we have the right kind of chacter. Kant doesn’t – as far as I know – leave open this possibility, but he could. xxx

 [u33] Look for what Kant says the correlate of wish in the realm of feeling.