Philosophy 202 (Fall 2014)
Readings in the Western Philosophical
Tradition: Modern Philosophy
Prof. Patrick Frierson
Class Meets: Olin East 129, Tuesday and
Thursday 2:30-4:00
Office Hours (Olin E124): Tuesday 4-5,
Wednesday 1-3, and by appointment
Goals: With respect to content,
this course focuses on central epistemological and metaphysical arguments of
key European philosophers of the modern period (1600-1800). The philosophers on whom we will focus are
Rene Descartes, Baruch Spinoza, Anne Conway, John Locke, George Berkeley, David
Hume, and Immanuel Kant. The early
modern period was particularly rich in excellent philosophy, however, so there
will be additional opportunities to study the thought of other figures in 17th
and 18th century European philosophy throughout the course.
Throughout our study of these
philosophers, we will focus on six key philosophical problems:
(1)
To what extent is it possible to have knowledge of anything?
(2)
How should we philosophically address the (epistemological) problem of human
diversity, that is, that people see the world in different (and incompatible)
ways?
(3)
What is the ultimate nature of all reality?
(4)
What is the human being? (In particular: Are human beings free? and What is the connection between the mind and the body?)
(5)
What is the nature of causation? How does one
thing cause changes in another? (Particularly, how do the mind and body
interact?)
(6)
Does God exist? If so, what is the nature of God and (how) can one have
knowledge of God?
With respect to skills, this course will help you develop as a
philosopher in four key respects.
1)
First and most importantly, you will
learn to be a better philosopher. A
philosopher is someone who pursues wisdom through careful reflection. In this course, our focus will be on
reflection that focuses on epistemological and metaphysical questions, but
throughout, you should keep in mind the ethical, political, and social
significance of these questions. We will
thus use modern philosophers to help our own philosophical reflection,
philosophizing with them and through
philosophical critique of them. By the end of
this course, you will learn how to follow through on philosophical insights in
historical and systematic ways.
2)
Second, we will read difficult texts
and read them carefully. Reading (and the related skill of listening) to
complex arguments expressed in unfamiliar terms will prepare you for engaging
with those who hold viewpoint or forms of expression different form your own,
and thus for thriving in an increasingly diverse world.
3)
Third, you will learn both to explain
the ideas of others and to articulate your own ideas orally and in
writing. Everyone is expected to
participate in class discussion in a respectful way, and one of the goals of this
course is to help all students develop confident, articulate, respectful modes
of oral communication. In addition,
everyone will write at least two papers over the course of the semester (see
details below on “writing papers in the history of philosophy”), and you will
have the opportunity to regularly submit drafts of written work for feedback.
4)
Fourth, though group assignments and
class discussions, you will learn to work effectively in a group settings and
will cultivate practices of respectful, productive, mutually-enriching,
philosophical interaction with your peers.
These skills will be cultivated
through several different kinds of assignments, some of which will also provide
the opportunity to learn (or apply) various technical skills, such as designing
and printing posters, producing and editing audio recordings, and so on, that
are relevant to the communication of your ideas. You have some flexibility about which
assignments you complete over the course of the semester. Some assignments are required of every
student, and each student must select other assignments to add up to a “full”
load of assignments for the course.
While not required, I particularly encourage students to complete
assignments that will push them to develop skills at which they might not think
of themselves as particularly excellent.
This course is an opportunity to learn and improve, and not primarily an opportunity to show how good you
already are.
With the exception of the final paper
and the quizzes, which count for all students, if a student completes more than
the required number of assignments, only the best 100% will be counted towards
her final grade.[1] All of these assignments are described in
detail at the end of the syllabus, but here is a brief snapshot of course
requirements:
Required
of all students: Reading
(0%) Participation
(0%) Quizzes
and Reading Guides (10%) Descartes
Paper (10%, due September 14) Final
Paper (30%, due December 14) |
Choose
enough to add up to 50% or more of your final grade: Group Projects
(Spinoza, Conway, Locke, Berkeley, and Hume; 20% each, due dates on timeline
below) Presentations
(Presentation options on timeline below, 10-20% each, depending upon whether
you do a paper along with your presentation) Philosophical exegesis paper (10%) Analytical critique paper
(10%) Mid-term exam
(20%) Final exam
(written: 30%, or oral: 20%) |
Optional Reading Group: I would love to form an optional reading group related to material from this class, one that would not count in any way towards your grade in the course (and to which you’d be more than welcome to invite friends not in this class). To make this truly optional, though, I’d like to pick material that will not be directly relevant to what we do in class. To that end, I’ve got two main ideas…two of the most impressive people during the period we cover in this class were Gottfried Leibniz and Margaret Cavendish. Both of them were involved in lots of not-strictly-philosophical endeavors while also being very impressive philosophers, and both get only scant coverage in this class. I’d be interested in a reading group on either of them…for Leibniz, I’m interested in reading a book called Leibniz and China, about Leibniz’s intense interest in Chinese (and Indian) philosophy. For Cavendish, I’d love to finally read her Blazing World, a philosophically rich work of science fiction. If anyone is interested in either reading group, let me know (sooner is better).
Class Time and Rules for Discussion: This class meets less than three hours a week, and most of the learning for the class occurs outside of our formal class meetings, through your own careful reading and thinking about the material, writing papers, working in groups (both formally and informally), and meetings with me during office hours.
Lectures. My goal is to use our class periods to accomplish goals that could not easily be accomplished outside of class. This will include some general lecturing, but I generally do not lecture extensively, for two reasons. First, extensive empirical (psychological) evidence and my own personal experience confirm that learning happens best through active engagement rather than passive listening. Thus much of what would normally go into lectures has been built into my “reading guides,” which help guide you through the readings without telling you precisely how to think about them. Second, lectures from me are not the best way to get expert commentary on the texts we are reading. Every figure that we read has at least one major entry in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, and most also have Cambridge Companions available in the library. These reference sources provide the highest quality commentary on the texts we are reading, and the Stanford Encyclopedia in particular is designed to be used by undergraduates at your level.
Discussions. The main use of our class time will be discussions amongst the entire class. These discussions provide ways to engage with the material in sustained ways, but they also – even more importantly – provide a context to practice the virtues of excellent participation in intellectual group discussion. These virtues include the following:
Preparation. You should come to class having read and thought about the material, so that you have an informed perspective on it.
Attentive listening. You should pay close attention to what I, and your peers, are saying. Whitman has excellent faculty, but we are the excellent college that we are because of the quality of our students. Your classmates have insightful things to contribute to our discussion; classmates comments are often more insightful than my own and are usually more directly relevant to your own readings of the texts.
Boldness and patience. Boldness and patience are both virtues in
conversation. You should participate, even
when you are not entirely sure that what you have to say is profound and
well-formulated, but you should also be patient, letting your own ideas mature
and providing opportunities for others to contribute to the conversation. Some of you will need to focus on boldness,
forcing yourselves to speak even before you are fully comfortable. (If you are one of these students, one good
practice is to prepare some comments and questions before class and to raise
these at the first opportunity. Another
good practice is to speak or raise your hand whenever there is more than 3
seconds of “dead time,” even if you don’t think what you have to say is
particularly profound.) Some will need
to focus on patience, holding back to practice attentive listening and to give
others the opportunity to contribute.
(If you are one of these, one good practice is to count to five before
speaking or raising your hand. Another
is to take the time to find textual support for your views before you
articulate them.)
Respectful engagement with others’ views. I expect you to engage with one another’s comments in class. Discussions should not be public dialogues with me. This engagement will often involve answering or refining another student’s question, taking another student’s point further, providing additional textual support for a point that a classmate makes, and so on. Engagement also can and often should involve criticism of the views of others, but such criticism should always remain respectful. Everyone in this room (including myself) is in the process of learning to philosophize well. When we criticize one another, it should be in the spirit of helping each other to develop as philosophers, not in an attempt to show that one person is better than another.
Growth mindset. Just as you engage respectfully with others, respect those who engage with your own views. My assumption in this course is that every comment that everyone makes (including myself) is provisional. In class, we are trying to benefit from our conversation, not to score points in it. And that means that when others offer objections or criticisms of your comments in class, these are not evidence of your inadequacy as a philosopher; they are opportunities for you (and your interlocutor) to grow. You should defend your view as effectively as you can, but you should also change your view when you come to see that it is not defensible.
“Class participation.” Participation is not any particular portion of your grade, but your participation can have a significant impact on your final grade. When evaluating participation, however, I am not interested merely in the quantity of comments. A student who dominates class discussion but fails to show the virtues listed above may have their overall grade lowered due to poor participation. A student who speaks occasionally but in well-informed, respectful, growing ways may have their grade raised. (A student who never speaks in class, however, cannot effectively demonstrate the above virtues.) If you are concerned about your participation, either because you fear participating too much or too little, please ask me about it at any time.
Small Group Work. Occasionally, we will divide the class into small groups for more focused work. This provides those who might be timid in a large group setting an opportunity to participate more actively, and it provides a different – and often healthy – dynamic for discussion. All of the virtues listed above apply to work in small groups. In addition, it is particularly important in these groups that students remain “on task.”
Timeline of Readings and Assignments
|
Reading (Except where noted, page numbers refer to
the 2009 edition of Ariew and Watkins, Modern Philosophy) |
Topics for Discussion |
Assignments (boldface refers to something you need to turn in to me) |
Sept. 2 |
Descartes’s selections from Discourse and Meditation 1 (AW 25-42) Consult the Descartes Reading Guide (html
or pdf)
as you read. In class, we will read selections
from Bacon (in AW 16-20); Montaigne (“Of
Cannibals”); deGournay (handout); and Galileo
(in AW 21-24). |
–Nature/origins of modern philosophy –Intro Descartes’s philosophy –Purpose of Meditations –D’s skeptical arguments
–Expectations for course |
Decide which philosophical problem you will address in your
paper and come up with a more specific question related to that problem. You should decide this based more on your
interests than the reading. |
Sept. 4 |
Descartes’s
Meditations 1-3 & selected
objections and replies 43-54, 69-72, 76-82 |
–Overcoming skepticism: “I am” –Nature of the self –Nature of knowledge (wax) –Proof(s) of God’s existence –Overcoming skepticism: God |
Check out an online resource, the Philosophy
Writing Tutor, for general advice on writing philosophy papers. Think about where Descartes has or will
address your topic most directly, and also about indirect ways in which his
discussion is relevant to your topic.
This may require reading/skimming ahead. Complete the “getting
started” part of the Writing Tutor. |
Sept. 9 |
Descartes’s
Meditations 2-6 &
selected objections and replies 47-68, 72-75, 86b (especially “my only remaining
concern…”), 92b (especially
“finally, as to the fact”) |
–Proof(s) of God’s existence –Overcoming skepticism: God –Problem of Error –Human Freedom –A Cartesian Circle? |
Complete
a first rough draft of your papers.
You should email these to me no later than midnight tonight (Sept. 9). (I will
not read or comment on these papers, but you need to email them to me so that
I know you are on track. If you have
specific questions about your paper, please ask those in the body of your
email. I will reply to as many of
these as I can.) [2] |
Sept 11 |
Descartes’s
Meditations 5-6 58-68 Selections from the correspondence between Descartes and Princess Elizabeth (read the first 8 pages – not including the intro material – of the file available here). |
–Proof of external world –Proof of Mind-body distinctness –Mind-body relationship –Problem of sensory error/nature of sensory knowledge – PAPER WORKSHOP: For a
portion of class, we will divide into pairs to help each other refine the
arguments of our papers. |
Revise your paper, including making sure
that the paper includes the following: – A very clear articulation of your
thesis – Clear guideposts that tell the
reader how each paragraph contributes to your overall argument – Strong textual support for your
interpretive claims – At least one (ideally two) of the
strongest possible objections to the thesis you are defending, along with
your responses to those objections.[3] Finish your Descartes papers. FINAL
DRAFTS OF YOUR DESCARTES PAPERS ARE DUE BY NOON ON SUNDAY, SEPTEMBER 14.
EMAILED TO ME AT frierspr@whitman.edu
WITH YOUR NAME AT THE START OF THE FILENAME.[4] POSSIBLE PRESENTATION: ·
DESCARTES’S ETHICS ·
ELIZABETH ·
ARNAULD ·
HOBBES |
Sept. 16 |
Spinoza,
Ethics, Part V, Prop. 42 and Part
1, through Prop. 14 (AW 195, 144-149) You should consult this Spinoza
Reading Guide as you read. I would also encourage all students
to make use of the Spinoza worksheet , even if you aren’t turning it
in as part of a group. |
–Blessedness –Spinoza’s philosophical method –Definitions and Axioms –Proof of God’s existence (P11) –Monism (P14) |
–Complete the Spinoza worksheet for
Proposition 11, 14. ·
–Come
to class with specific questions for or challenges of at least two
definitions, axioms, or proofs. |
Sept. 18 |
Spinoza, Ethics, Pt. 1 (entire); Pt. 2., Def’ns,
Axioms, and Propositions 1, 2, 7, 11-14 (You should also read the
propositions, but not the proofs, for the rest of part 2.) |
–Monism (P14) –Universal determinism of finite things (P28) –Against religious prejudices (Appendix) –Nature of the human mind (based on Pt. 2) |
–Revise/correct worksheet for P11, P14 –Complete worksheet for P28, Pt. 2, P7. –Come ready to discuss Part One: P11, P14, P28; and come with
some sense of Spinoza’s philosophy of mind. |
Sept. 23 |
Spinoza, Ethics,
Pt. 2, PP. 40-44 (focus on the kinds of knowledge), Pt. 5, Preface and
P21-28, 42 (AW 179-83, 188-95) |
–Types of knowledge –Highest end of human beings (P 25) –Comparison of Spinoza and Descartes |
–Come ready to discuss Part One: P11, P14, P28; Part Two: P40,
and Part Five: P42. SPINOZA GROUP PROJECTS MUST BE
EMAILED TO ME BY 5 PM ON SUNDAY, SEPT 28. |
Sept. 25 |
Conway, Principles,
etext available here. Chapters I; II; III.1-5, 8, 10; IV.1; V.6
(V.1, 3, and 7 are recommended but optional), (pp. 9-17, 18, 20-21, and 26-7 in the 1996
Cambridge Edition) Consult
the Conway
Reading Guide as you read. |
-- Conway’s conception of God -- argument for the “mediator” -- nature of time -- freedom (divine and created) -- infinity of creatures (nature of and argument for) |
|
Sept. 30 |
Conway, Principles,
Chapters VI.1-6, 11; VII summary, 4; VIII.1 and last 2¶s of 2; IX), pp. 28-35, 41, 51-3, 54-5, 56-7, 58, 63-70. |
--monism of created substance (nature of,
argument for) -- unity of spirit and body -- nature of body-spirit interactions -- vitalism -- nature of motion -- nature of causation --Conway’s epistemology (p. 54 but also
throughout book) --Conway vs. Descartes and Spinoza |
|
Oct. 2 |
Conway (review all readings); Leibniz, Monadology, entire 275-83 (Recommended: Discourse on Metaphysics 30-32, pp. 242-244) Consult the Leibniz Reading Guide (html
or pdf)
as you read. |
–nature and types of monads –God’s existence –interactions amongst monads (e.g. mind-body) –preestablished harmony –theodicy/best of all worlds –human freedom –principles of contradiction and sufficient
reason –comparison of Leibniz with Conway |
POSSIBLE PRESENTATIONS: ·
LEIBNIZ ·
VOLTAIRE ·
MADAME DU CHATELET ·
SAMUEL CLARKE |
Oct. 7 |
Spinoza, Conway, Leibniz review (Reread all, especially Leibniz) |
|
|
Oct. 7 or 8 (precise time TBD) |
Optional: Review Session for Mid-Term |
|
For a list of topics you should study for
the mid-term, click here. For a sample of the mid-term format, click here. Mid-terms will be handed out on Oct. 4 and
due on Oct. 9th. |
Oct. 9 |
Mind and Body Day 1. Descartes’s Meditations AW 61-68 2.
Correspondence between Elizabeth
and Descartes (read the first 8 pages – not including the intro material – of
the file available here). 3. Malebranche, The Search
after Truth, (AW 212-215). 4. Hobbes, Leviathan, chapters I, ii, and vi (focus on the first few paragraphs), available online here. See too Objection IV on p. 78b in AW. 5. Spinoza Bk 2, PP11-14 and skim through at least P23 (AW 168-72, and skim 172-75). 6. Conway, Principles, ch.
VII-VIII (pp. 41-62) 7. Leibniz, Monadology, §§17, 25, 50-52, 62-64, 78-83 8. Possible readings from MARGARET
CAVENDISH |
OVERVIEW OF EARLY MODERN CONCEPTIONS OF THE
MIND-BODY RELATIONSHIP AND VARIOUS ANSWERS TO ELIZABETH’S QUESTION ABOUT
MIND-BODY INTERACTION. MID-TERM HANDED OUT. |
MID-TERM HANDED OUT. On this day, we will break into small groups. You’ll be assigned to a group at the end of
class on Oct. 7. For Oct. 9, you need
to come with a clear explanation and defense of the views on the relationship
between mind and body of your philosopher.
You also need to be familiar enough with the views of others to defend
your views to them. POSSIBLE PRESENTATIONS: ·
MALEBRANCHE ·
HOBBES ·
MARGARET CAVENDISH |
Oct. 14 October Break |
October Break |
October Break |
October Break |
Oct. 16 |
Locke’s Essay
Bk I, ch 1, Bk II, chs
1-2, 5-12 (especially ch. 8 ¶¶9-23) Leibniz’s New Essays, selection AW 316-18, 322-42, 422-425a Consult the Locke
Reading Guide as you read. |
–Locke’s critique of innate ideas –Leibniz’s response (particularly focus on the marble analogy) –Locke’s epistemological turn –origin of ideas –sensation vs. reflection –primary vs. secondary qualities |
CONWAY GROUP ASSIGNMENTS MUST BE
EMAILED (OR DELIVERED) TO ME NO LATER THAN 9 AM ON FRIDAY, OCTOBER 17TH. –Prepare for debate between Locke and Leibniz
about the legitimacy of innate ideas.
(You should be ready to defend either position; I’ll assign you at the
start of class.) |
Oct. 21 |
Locke’s Essay
Bk II, chs 21, 23 AW 348-367 |
MID-TERM DUE –idea of power –human free will –ideas of substances |
MID-TERM DUE |
Oct. 23 |
Locke’s Essay
IV.1-3, 10-15, especially IV.1-3, IV.10; IV.11¶¶8-14; IV.15¶¶1-5 AW 386-97, 399, 405-411, 413-14,
415-17 |
–nature and extent of knowledge (compare with Descartes) –mind–body relationship –knowledge of God –knowledge of existence –probability |
LOCKE GROUP PROJECTS MUST BE EMAILED
TO ME NO LATER THAN 5PM ON SUNDAY, OCTOBER 26. |
Oct. 28 |
Cockburn, Defense of Mr. Locke’s Essay, selections Damaris Cudworth
(Lady Masham), Discourse
on the Love of God, selections Masham, selections from correspondence |
|
|
Oct. 30 |
Berkeley, Principles 435-448 Consult the Berkeley
Reading Guide as you read. |
–skepticism –abstract ideas –esse
is percepi –primary and secondary qualities |
|
Nov. 4 |
Berkeley, Principles 446-453 |
–vs. ideas of substances, powers, etc –minds –God –natural laws |
BERKELEY GROUP ASSIGNMENTS (IN .MP3 FORMAT)
SHOULD BE EMAILED TO ME NO LATER THAN 5 PM ON SUNDAY, NOVEMBER 9TH. THIS MEANS THAT YOU NEED TO CONDUCT YOUR
DISCUSSIONS AS SOON AS POSSIBLE AFTER CLASS ON OCTOBER 25TH SO
THAT YOU WILL BE ABLE TO DO THE NECESSARY EDITING. |
Nov. 6 |
Hume’s Enquiry
§§ 1-7 533-564 Consult the Hume
Reading Guide as you read. |
–ideas and impressions –matters of fact vs. relations of ideas –Hume on the importance and legitimacy of causal inferences –Causation |
|
Nov. 11 |
Hume’s Enquiry
§§ 6-8, 10 555-575, 577-586 Possible selections from Reid or Rousseau Optional readings: Hume’s Enquiry
§12 Hume’s Treatise
I.v-vi 593-600, 517-32 |
–Causation –Human freedom –Miracles Optional readings cover: –mitigated skepticism –self-knowledge –personal identity |
POSSIBLE PRESENTATIONS: ·
HUME’S MORAL THEORY ·
ADAM SMITH ·
THOMAS REID ·
JEAN-JACQUES ROUSSEAU |
Nov 13 |
Freedom and Necessity |
On this day, we will break into 6
(or more) groups. You’ll be assigned
to a group at the end of class on Nov. 11.
For Nov. 13, you need to come with a clear explanation and defense of
the views on human freedom (and its relationship with necessity) of your
philosopher. You also need to be
familiar enough with the views of others to defend your views to them. HUME GROUP ASSIGNMENTS MUST BE EMAILED TO ME
NO LATER THAN 5 PM ON SUNDAY, NOV 16. |
|
Nov 18 |
FINAL PAPER WORKSHOP |
Drafts of your final paper must be
emailed to me no later than 9 AM on November 17. You should also bring a hard copy of your
paper to class. |
|
Nov. 20 |
Skepticism and Its Discontents OR Dealing with Globalization and Diversity
(Specific Readings TBD) |
|
|
|
THANKSGIVING |
VACATION |
If
you want comments on a draft of your final paper, you must email that draft
to me by midnight on Wednesday, Nov. 26. |
Dec. 2 |
Kant, Critique
of Pure Reason 717-737 + this short online handout Consult the Kant
Reading Guide. |
–Kant’s “Copernican turn” –analytic vs. synthetic/a priori vs. a posteriori –problem of a priori synthetic knowledge –proof that space (and time) are a priori intuitions –transcendental idealism |
|
Dec. 4 |
Kant, Critique
of Pure Reason 722, 729-37, 768-779 |
–a priori concepts –argument for substance –argument for causation (vs. Hume) |
|
Dec. 9 |
Kant, Critique
of Pure Reason 724a, 768-779, 798-800, 811-19,
handout (from Critique of Practical
Reason) |
–possibility of human freedom |
|
Dec. 11 |
Catch up and Review |
Catch up and Review |
|
Dec. 15 |
FINAL EXAM at 2 PM. |
For a list of topics
you should study for the mid-term (including possible essay questions), click
here. |
FINAL PAPERS DUE SUNDAY, DEC 14ST,
AT 5 PM, emailed to me at frierspr@whitman.edu. (Students taking the final exam may have an
extension, if requested in advance,
until Tuesday, December 16, at midnight.)
Students who would like comments on previous drafts of their final
papers should email them to me no later than Wednesday, NOV. 26TH. |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Course Assignments
Reading and Participation: All
students are expected to come to every class having read the assigned material at least twice and to have thought carefully
about it. I do not necessarily expect you to have a complete understanding of
the material, but you should read carefully and repeatedly until you have a
good understanding of much of what is assigned, and for the material that you
do not understand, you should come to class with specific questions about what you do not understand. If I call on
you to explain a particular passage, you should not respond “I didn’t get that
passage.” Instead, you should say, “Well, I thought that Spinoza meant
such-and-such, but then I couldn’t figure out how to reconcile that
understanding with what he said later, when he said this-and-that, since
this-and-that seems to conflict with such-and-such in this particular way.” If your understanding is still at the “I
don’t get it” level, then you have more work to do. If it’s at the “I thought that . . . but . .
.,” then I have work to do.
In addition, I have provided Reading Guides for most of the readings
we will do in the course. You should
make use of these readings guides as you read and reread. You need not provide written answers to every
question, but you should think about
every question, and writing out answers is strongly recommended. I may check these guides occasionally, I will
feel free to call on any student to give their answer to any question in the
reading guide, and they will inform my decisions about what to include in
quizzes.
Participation in class discussion is an essential part of
the class, and I may alter final grades either up or down, depending upon your
participation over the course of the semester, but participation is not worth
any particular percentage of your grade.
Note that your participation grade is based on the quality of participation, not the quantity. You should contribute thoughtful comments to class discussion in a respectful way. For some of
you, this will mean preparing oral comments before class and making a conscious
effort to speak. For others, it will
mean holding yourself back when you find yourself to be dominating
discussion. If you desire an assessment
of your participation at any point in the semester, please feel free to ask me
about it.
The book for this class is available in the Whitman Bookstore: Roger
Ariew, Eric Watkins, eds., Modern
Philosophy: An Anthology of Primary Sources (Indianapolis:
Hackett, 2009). Page numbers in the timeline refer to the SECOND edition (2009) of
this book, which is
the edition we will use in this class.
Some material will be provided in supplements available on our Cleo site
or from links provided directly on the syllabus.
Quizzes: Most class periods will
begin with a short quiz on the reading for the day. If you have followed the advice above, you
should do just fine on the quizzes.
Occasionally, I may orally “cold-call” on students to talk about their
responses to various parts of the reading guide. Responses that show a failure to have read
the material attentively will count against a students’ quiz grade.
Deadlines: All
assignments for this course should be turned in at the date and time for which
they are due. I will give a one hour
grace period after assignments are due, but after that grace period,
assignments that are turned in late will immediately be penalized by one full
grade point, and the grade will drop by an addition one point every 24
hours. (Thus an assignment that is A quality work but 61 minutes late will get a B. The same
assignment, 75 hours late, will get an F.)
I highly recommend turning in your assignments – especially group
assignments – early, and all members of a team will be held responsible for the
failure of any one member to get work done on time. (The one exception to this policy is the
final paper. Students who have a good
reason for needing a later deadline on the final paper, and who ask for that
later deadline at least one week before the paper is due, will be granted a
later deadline.)
Written assignments: All
written assignments, including your papers and your group assignments, should
be submitted to me by email. To submit work
by email, you should email your work in .doc or .docx
format to frierspr@whitman.edu. You must include your first and last name as
the first terms in the filename, and the rest of the filename should make clear
what assignment you are turning in. (So, for instance, when Jane Doe turns in
her Descartes paper, she should save the paper under the filename “jane doe descartes paper.doc”.
Papers saved with the wrong filename will not be read by me. For group projects, you should save the paper
with the last name of every group participant in the filename (e.g. “doe lopez mccarty
lee spinoza project.doc”). More specific information on each assignment
is below.
Exams: All exams will be closed book and will involve quotation
identification, short (1-3 paragraph) response questions, and at least one
longer essay question. The midterm will
be a take-home exam, for which you will be allowed two hours, though it should
not take this long. The final will be in
class at our regularly scheduled final exam time (thus you will have 2
hours). Review sheets are available on
the timeline above (where the exam appears).
Group Assignments: This course is organized around a series of
philosophers, for each of which (with the exceptions of Descartes and Kant)
there are specific projects. I have found these projects to be conducive to
learning the material, so I encourage every student to work on every assignment
throughout the semester, but you will also have the opportunity to work on some
of these assignments for credit. To get
credit for an assignment, you must work on it in a group (of 3-5 students), and
you will be graded on the project as a whole.
Each of these projects can be worth up to 20% of your final grade in the
course. Of that, approximately 15% will
be a group grade, based on the overall quality of the finished product produced
by your group.[5] The remaining 5% will be an individual grade,
based on self- and peer-assessments. For
each group assignment, the group as a whole should send me the finished
product, and each member of the group should send me an email with a short
assessment of the performance of her/himself and of each of the other members
of the group. You should provide a “score” for yourself and your peers, from 1
to 7, along with a short explanation of why you gave that score. In scoring
your teammates, you should focus not merely on specific content that group
members may have contributed, but also to the effect that the group member had
on the dynamics of the group. (A brilliant interpreter of Locke who is hostile
and uncooperative may get a 1. A student who struggles to understand very basic
arguments in Descartes but is able to ask questions well and get his teammates
to cooperate in completing the assignment well might get a 6 or 7.) I very strongly encourage you to be fair with
your assessments, both of yourself and of your teammates, and you should give
at most one score above five (and even that, only if truly warranted). Here is the meaning I intend for you to give
to the scores you assign:
1 = Unacceptable performance. This group member did not contribute to the
success of the group, and/or may even have slowed us down.
2 = Very poor. This group member contributed something, but
either the quantity or the quality of his/her contributions were very weak.
Virtually none of his/her contributions showed up in the final result, or if
they did, group members regret not having the time to change these
contributions.
3 = Below Average. This group member made real and positive
contributions that improved the final product, but not in ways as significant
or pervasive as I expect of a typical Whitman student.
4 = Average/Good. This group member did her/his duty,
contributing a reasonable amount of reasonably high quality insight, thought,
hard work, and cooperative engagement with the group. Her/his ideas made a
significant and positive contribution to the final product. (This should be the
standard default score.)
5 = Very good. This group member went above and beyond what
one would expect of a typical member of a group. S/he had insights far beyond
other members of the group, and/or raised important questions that focused on
key issues, and/or explained difficult material to other group members in particularly
clear and helpful ways, and/or helped organize or motivate the rest of the
group in particularly important ways. (You should give at most one score above
5.)
6 = Excellent. This group member transformed the group in a
way that made the final product and the overall experience manifestly better
than they would otherwise have been. S/he was a de facto team leader,
motivating and organizing us, and s/he contributed in essential and
irreplaceable ways to our performance as a team. (You should give at most one score above 5.)
7 = Extraordinary. I could not have imagined a team member as
valuable as this one. S/he should be hired as a Whitman professor,
or at least as TA for this class next year. (You should give at most one score
of 7 during the course of the semester.)
Specific information on each group
assignment is below.
Presentations: Over the course of the semester, there will be
several opportunities for students to give presentations on important early
modern philosophers that we will not read for this course. Any student is free
to sign up for these class presentations. If no students
sign up for a given philosopher, we will not discuss that philosopher in this
course. If more than 3 students sign up for a particular philosopher, only the
first three who sign up will be allowed to present (as a group) on that
philosopher. You must sign up at least 10 days before the scheduled
presentation. Students who sign up for presentations will need to read primary
sources by this person and secondary sources about them, and then pick a short
selection (no more than 10 pages, preferably less than 5 pages) for your
classmates to read that will give the main points and at least one major
argument of the philosopher. (These selections must be made available to your
classmates the class period prior to your presentation. You may either email
the class with a link, document, or PDF; or bring 25 copies of the reading to
hand out in class.) On the day of the presentation, students will be expected
to give a short presentation (no more than 10 minutes) providing an overview of
the philosopher on whom they are presenting. This overview should go
substantially beyond the assigned readings; the idea is to give fellow students
a sense for the philosopher as a whole. On these days, our class discussion
will incorporate the readings from these philosophers.
For full credit (20%), students must
prepare a paper (1500-3000 words) outlining the key aspects of the philosopher
on whom they presented and briefly (up to 500 words) assessing the treatment
that their philosopher received during class discussion. While you may include a brief biography of
the thinker, these papers should emphasize the philosophical ideas and
arguments of the philosopher. You should
give at least some overview of the philosophical views as a whole, but you may
focus your discussion on one or two ideas that you find most interesting and
important. It is also appropriate to
make connections with other philosophers in the course, though this should be
done in ways that help elucidate the core ideas of the philosopher you
presented on.
For presentations by groups of more
than one, each person should also submit a very brief self/peer assessment (as
for group assignments).
You can find information about almost
all of the figures you are expected to present on in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy and
on many of them in the in the Cambridge History of Seventeenth Century Philosophy
(on reserve). You can also find
information on many modern philosophers not mentioned in the syllabus. If you would like to present on a figure who is not included, you will probably be able to do so if
you let me know early in the semester so that I can schedule an appropriate
class time for your presentation. Cambridge Companions are also good
places to start in investigating these philosophers (The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes, for instance.) You are expected
to make use of both primary and secondary sources in preparing your
presentation, and I strongly encourage you to come to me for help in tracking
these down. You must make use of at least some
non-electronic resources in preparing your presentation. (Incidentally,
while very helpful in some respects, Wikipedia
does
not constitute a legitimate source of information for your presentations.)
Course Papers
One of the main skills that you will learn
in this class is the integration of historical-philosophical sources into
papers in which you defend your own answer to an important philosophical
problem. For both of the required papers
for the class, I will be looking for a clear, complex, interesting, and
controversial thesis that is defended with compelling philosophical arguments
in precise, elegant, and grammatically correct prose. Both papers will also involve interaction
with historical philosophical arguments, and I am looking for a use of such
arguments that goes beyond a mere “compare and contrast” essay and instead
engages with well-articulated and textually-defended interpretations of
historical philosophers in ways that advance your own philosophical argument.
Descartes Paper (10%, due NOON
ON SUNDAY, SEPTEMBER 14): This assignment is required for all
students. At the end of the
first unit of the course (on Descartes), you will write a paper related to one
of the five philosophical problems listed above (knowledge, reality, human being,
causation, or God). In this paper, you
should articulate a specific question related to your problem, one narrower
than the question above. (For example,
instead of “to what extent is it possible to have knowledge of anything?” you
might ask, “How can one respond to the skeptical arguments against the senses
that Descartes lays out in Meditation One?” or “What kind of knowledge is
possible of the physical world?”) You
should defend a specific thesis that answers this question, and you should use
Descartes in the course of defending that thesis. (We will discuss in class ways for using
Descartes to defend your own thesis.)
This paper will be a first try at what you will end up doing for your
course paper at the end of the semester, so while you will not be bound to use
the same topic for the final paper, you are encouraged to choose a topic you
will want to think about for the rest of the semester. This paper should be no less than 800 and no
more than 1500 words.
Course Paper (30%, due December 14): This assignment is required for all
students. Over the course of the
semester, you will write a single, complex paper, answering a question related
to one of the five philosophical problems listed above (knowledge, reality,
human being, causation, or God). By the end of the semester, you will write a
paper of no less than 1500 and no more than 2500 words that engages with at
least three of the philosophers we study over the course of the semester and
defends a clear, complex, interesting, and controversial thesis that answers a
question related to (but more specific than) the question listed above.[6]
While your final paper is not due until December
14, you should work on it throughout the semester. Over the course of the
semester, you should update your final paper, refining your topic, question,
and thesis; and incorporating arguments from philosophers as we read them. I strongly encourage you to submit new paper
drafts after each major philosopher, incorporating material from that
philosopher into your final paper.
Throughout the course of the semester, in addition to adding
perspectives of new philosophers, you should refine the question you aim to
answer and gradually form your own ideas about how best to answer that
question, drawing from your interactions with the philosophers we are studying.
Before submitting the final draft, you will also need to decide which figures
are the most important to include in the final draft, and you will have to cut
material that is less relevant in order to ensure that you do justice to your
topic, defend your thesis adequately, and include sufficient treatments of the
three philosophers on whom you focus. The final draft of the paper will be due
on December 14.
Philosophical exegesis paper (10%) Your final paper and paper on Descartes must
offer your own answer to a
philosophical problem, drawing from major historical figures. But historians of philosophy often write
papers that purport to elucidate the ideas of a philosopher without necessarily
defending those ideas as their own. Papers in philosophical exegesis generally
start with a puzzle of interpretation.
For example, Anne Conway says that there is only one created
“substance,” but also that there are infinitely many created things; so what
precisely does she mean by “substance”?
Or, for another example, Berkeley does not explicitly talk about the
nature of human freedom; given what he does say, what is his likely view on
this matter? The paper then proceeds to
answer these questions, considering various possible interpretations and
defending one’s own on the basis of specific textual support, plausibility in
the light of other claims the philosopher has made, and general philosophical
plausibility. Any student can write a
philosophical exegesis paper on any of the philosophers we read in this
course. Such papers are due at the same
time as the group project for that philosopher, and they should be 1500-2500
words in length.
Analytical critique paper (10%). Where
the philosophical exegesis paper is more
historical than the final paper, the analytical critique paper is less historical. For this paper, you should take an idea or
argument from one of the philosophers we have read and engage with that
argument in your own terms. “Critique”
here need not mean criticism of the argument or position; though it often will
involve criticism, one might also extend a point made by a philosopher or show
that an argument made in one context applies equally well in another. The distinguishing feature of this paper is
that the majority of the paper will be philosophical argument rather than interpretation. As with all papers, but particularly for
these, it is important that the thesis be clearly articulated and that you be
able to see how the thesis is controversial
and even prima facie implausible. Thus, arguing that Descartes was wrong to
think that an the existence of an evil demon would
make our beliefs unreliable could be a worthwhile thesis. Arguing that he was wrong
to think that the pineal gland is the physical seat of the soul would not
be. These papers are due at the same
time as the group project for that philosopher, and they should be 1500-2500
words in length.
Group Assignment #1: Spinoza Worksheet – Due 5
PM ON SUNDAY, SEPT 28RD
For each proposition below, work
through Spinoza’s whole proof. I recommend reading through the assigned
reading in the order Spinoza presents it, and then working backwards through
each key proposition’s proof, tracing back to the axioms and definitions on
which it ultimately depends. When you finally turn in the worksheet, you
should have clearly written answers to each question. (Answers to part
(a) can take the form of a simple “yes” or “no.” All other questions
should be answered with at least one clear and concise paragraph.)
1. Prop 11: God . . . necessarily
exists.
a) Does Spinoza
successfully prove proposition 11?
b) If not, what specific inferences are invalid, what specific axioms
are false, and/or what specific definitions are illegitimate? (In
answering this question, be prepared to explain in precisely what sense the
inferences are invalid, the axioms are false, or the definitions are
illegitimate; and also be sure that you have identified the precise role that
such inferences, axioms, or definitions play in Spinoza’s argument.)
c) Without considering Spinoza’s subsequent
argument about the nature of God, what significance would P 11 have for
Spinoza’s contemporaries (e.g. Descartes)?
d) Without considering Spinoza’s subsequent
argument about the nature of God, what significance would believing it have
for us?
2. Prop. 14: There can be . . .
no other substance but God.
a) Explain P 14
without using any of Spinoza’s technical vocabulary, in a way that would make
sense and be interesting to a friend who had never read any philosophy.
b) Given
Prop 11, does Spinoza successfully prove proposition 14?
c) If not, what
specific inferences are invalid, what specific axioms are false, and/or what
specific definitions are illegitimate? (In answering this question, be
prepared to explain in precisely what sense the inferences are invalid, the
axioms are false, or the definitions are illegitimate.) In particular,
are there any invalid inferences between P11 and P14 (or
any new axioms or definitions of which Spinoza makes use that are
problematic)? That is, is Spinoza correct that if God
necessarily exists, then there can be no substance but God?
d) What
significance would believing P 14 have for Spinoza’s contemporaries (e.g.
Descartes)?
e) What
significance would believing it have for us?
3. Prop. 28: Every individual
thing . . ..
a)
Explain P 14 without using any of
Spinoza’s technical vocabulary, in a way that would make sense and be
interesting to a friend who had never read any philosophy.
b)
Given Props 11 and 14, does Spinoza
successfully prove proposition 28?
c)
If not, what specific inferences are
invalid, what specific axioms are false, and/or what specific definitions are
illegitimate? (In answering this question, be prepared to explain in
precisely what sense the inferences are invalid, the axioms are false, or the
definitions are illegitimate.)
d)
What significance would believing P 28
have for Spinoza’s contemporaries (e.g. Descartes)?
e)
What significance would believing it
have for us?
4. Book II, Prop. 7: The order and
connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of things.
a) What is the
significance of P 7 within Spinoza’s Ethics? (For example, what significance does it play
in understanding the definitions to part I)
b) What
significance would believing P 7 have for Spinoza’s contemporaries (e.g.
Descartes)?
c) What
significance would believing it have for us?
5. Book V, Prop 25. For analyzing this Proposition, you should
use the hypertext edition of Spinoza’s Ethics, available at http://www.mtsu.edu/~rbombard/RB/Spinoza/ethica-front.html.
a) What do you think
would be the most problematic aspects of Spinoza’s proof of proposition 25?
b) What
significance would believing it have for us? (Here take into account,
too, Book V, P42.)
Group
Assignment #2: You may choose ONE of these projects
Due
MIDNIGHT ON FRIDAY, OCTOBER 17
Group
Assignment #2a: Conway Comparison Poster
For this project, you should put together a poster comparing Conway’s philosophy with one or two other philosophers we’ve discussed this semester. You should lay out the poster to present the information most effectively. You should include whatever material you think interesting and important, but you should discuss at least six of the following topics and compare philosophers with respect to them.
· Nature of substance
· Number of substance(s)
· Relationship between mind and body (including, if applicable, how one causes changes in the other or seems to cause such changes)
· Nature of Causation in general (e.g. how one body changes or seems to change another)
· Knowledge (how do we gain knowledge? What is knowledge?)
· The nature of human freedom
· The nature of God (including divine freedom)
· How philosophers should deal with diversity/pluralism
· The ultimate goal of human life
Group
Assignment #2b: Conway (or Leibniz) in Preschool
Jack and Jill went up the hill,
To fetch a pail of water;
Jack fell down, and broke his crown,
And Jill came tumbling after.
In your translation, use as many technical
terms as possible, and use them as effectively as possible. (If necessary, include footnotes explaining
your interpretative decisions). You
should also illustrate the main features of Conway’s (or Leibniz’s) philosophy
in your translation (e.g. re: Conway, being sure to mention the mediator and
why this mediator is necessary; or re: Leibniz, being sure to discuss the
notion of the best of all possible worlds).
If you want to get very creative, you
could even transform the rhyme into a dialogue, something like:
Leibniz: “The monad that was Jack . .
.” (translating the first two lines).
Conway: “Ah yes, but don’t forget
Jill, the creature God made …” (retranslating the first two lines).
Leibniz: “Yes, the monad that was Jill
was also there, but then Jack …”
translating the third line.
Conway: “Ah, but then Jill…” (translating the fourth line).
And then a witty punch-line. J
Group
Assignment #3: Lockean Poetics
Due
5PM ON SUNDAY, OCTOBER 26th
Analyze a poem in terms of Locke's Essay. While you may present
your results in the form of a paper, I encourage you to do a poster or any
other format for which you get prior approval from me (e.g. a short play).[7] YOU MAY ANALYZE ANY POEM THAT YOU
CHOOSE. (For a complete and
searchable e-text of Locke’s Essay, click HERE.
And HERE is a great site for finding poems.)
The analysis should explain what sorts
of ideas are referred to by some representative words in the poem. (Aim to find
at least one example each of simple ideas of sensation, simple ideas of
reflection, complex ideas of sensation and complex
ideas of reflection. If possible, you also should give examples of primary and
secondary qualities in the poem.) You should analyze the literal meaning of the
poem, discussing whether it provides "knowledge" in Lockean terms, or probable opinion, or both or neither. But
you should also discuss what you take the main point of the poem to be, what
the poem teaches, what it does to the reader, and so
on. As a whole, does the poem provide "knowledge" in Lockean terms? If so, specifically how?
If not, is this a problem for the poem (or for Locke's theory of knowledge)?
Group Assignment #4: "Conversations with Berkeley"
(This assignment will be done in pairs.)
Due at 5 PM ON SUNDAY, NOVEMBER 9TH
For this assignment, you will need to help other people explain the most
important aspects of Berkeley's thought and then give their opinions about his
philosophy. First, you'll need to find two friends or acquaintances who have
never taken a philosophy class. Then, you'll need some sort of recording device
(a tape recorder, a microphone-computer set up, or something similar). Finally,
you'll need a comfortable place for a chat, and the requisite refreshments so
that you and your guest are comfortable. (Please avoid intoxicants until after
you have completed the assignment.) Once you are set up, the two of you simply
need to explain to your guests the basics of Berkeley's philosophy, answer
questions, clarify Berkeley’s views, find out what your guests find most
interesting about it . . . in other words, you need to have a conversation.
During this, you should take the stance of people defending
Berkeley's view. (Aim to be Berkeley-channelers.)
Your conversation should last at least an hour, and you should record the whole
conversation, but what you will actually turn in is three recordings of no more
than 5 minutes each (and no more than 10 minutes total). The first recording
should include what you think is the most interesting and important 5 minutes
of your conversation. The second recording should be the one in which your
guest most clearly explains Berkeley's thought and gives his or her opinion
about it. In the final recording (which you can make at a later time), you
should explain what was hardest to explain about Berkeley, and/or any
challenges that you encountered in the course of your conversation. (At the start
of the conversation, and at the start of the recording that you turn in, you
should have each participant in the conversation state their full name, year,
and major.)
For help setting up and/or editing these tapes,
you should contact Instructional Multimedia Services (see http://www.whitman.edu/content/wcts/ims/).
The recordings should all be converted into .mp3 or .wma or some other easily
readable digital form.
Group Assignment #5:
Hume across the disciplines
Due
by 5 PM ON SUNDAY, NOV. 16.
For
this assignment, you are to report on the implications of Hume's philosophy for
knowledge in disciplines other than philosophy. You may choose up to three knowledge-claims
made in another discipline or disciplines.
These should come from a textbook or equivalent (e.g. a scientific
article or a book of history). You
should provide quote the relevant claim or claims at the start of your report
and should provide me a .pdf or photocopy of the sections in the book(s) that
most directly argue for the claim(s).
You should then provide a Humean analysis of
these knowledge-claims. Do they really
count as knowledge? Why or why not? Why might they seem to be knowledge? Do they carry probability? What is the nature
and origin of belief in them? This
report can be presented as an essay, outline, poster, or in any format that
best presents Hume’s criticisms of the relevant knowledge-claims. The ideal length of a written commentary
would be 1500-2500 words.
[1] There is one other exception to this policy. Students who choose to do group assignments
and get very low peer reviews on those group assignments will have those
assignments count towards their final grade, even if they do better on other
assignments.
[2] At this stage, you should make sure that you have a clear,
complex, controversial, and interesting thesis statement. Your paper should have at least six
paragraphs, each of which clearly establishes one important point in support of
your overall thesis using philosophical and text-based argument. You should have several references to and/or
quotations of Descartes to support your arguments. You should either cut your
introduction entirely and leave just the thesis statement, or you should
actually use your introduction to advance your argument. NO FLUFF.
And you should make sure that the paper is grammatically perfect.
[3] Ideally, by the time you finish with this draft, your paper will
be too long. You should then shorten it by cutting material that is not
essential and by tightening up your writing.
[4] YOUR PAPER MUST BE IN .DOC
FORMAT AND THE FILENAME MUST BEGIN WITH YOUR FIRST AND LAST NAME. (E.g, if your name
is Jane Doe, you would send me a paper with a filename like ‘jane doe Descartes
paper.doc’)
[5] In special circumstances, I reserve the right to weigh the
individual portion of the grade more heavily.
This will be particularly relevant in cases where a particular student
makes an extraordinarily good or extraordinarily bad contribution to their
group.
[6] For example, you may start with “What is the human being?” and
end up with a paper that answers the question “Is freedom necessary for moral
responsibility?” by using Spinoza, Hume, and Kant to argue something like,
“While Kant thinks that he can preserve human freedom as a necessary condition
of the possibility of morality, his metaphysics in fact offers decisive reasons
to reject freedom. Fortunately, as Spinoza and Hume show in very different
ways, a robust conception of moral responsibility is consistent with this
rejection of freedom.”
[7] If you do a poster, play, or other non-electronic form of presentation, you should either turn the item in to my office or arrange with me for a means of performing it/turning it in.