Philosophy 202 (Fall 2017)
Readings in the Western Philosophical
Tradition: Modern Philosophy
Prof. Patrick Frierson
Class Meets: Olin 192, Tuesday and Thursday
10:00-11:20
Office Hours (Olin 194): Tuesday 4-5, Wednesday 10-noon, and by
appointment. I am often in the office late, particularly on Tuesday and Wednesday
nights, so I’m happy to meet with students in the evenings.
Required Texts:
Roger Ariew, Eric Watkins,
eds., Modern
Philosophy: An Anthology of Primary Sources (Indianapolis:
Hackett, 2009). Page
numbers in the timeline refer to the SECOND edition (2009) of this book, which is the edition we will use in this class.
Optional: Margaret Atherton, ed. Women Philosophers of the Early Modern Period, Indianapolis:
Hackett, 1994.
David Hume, An Enquiry Concerning
the Principles of Morals, Ed. Eric Steinberg, Indianapolis: Hackett, ISBN:
978-0915145454
Immanuel Kant, Groundwork
for the Metaphysics of Morals, Ed. Mary Gregor
and Jens Timmerman, Cambridge University Press, 2012, ISBN: 978-1107401068.
Goals: With respect to content, this course
focuses on central epistemological, metaphysical, and ethical arguments of key
European philosophers of the modern period (1600-1800). The philosophers on whom we will focus are
Rene Descartes, Elizabeth of Bohemia, Thomas Hobbes, Baruch Spinoza, John
Locke, David Hume, and Immanuel Kant.
The early modern period was particularly rich in excellent philosophy,
however, so there will be additional opportunities to study the thought of
other figures in 17th and 18th century European
philosophy throughout the course.
Throughout our study of these
philosophers, we will focus on seven key philosophical problems:
(1)
To what extent is it possible to have knowledge of anything?
(2)
How should we philosophically address the (epistemological) problem of human
diversity, that is, that people see the world in different (and incompatible)
ways?
(3)
What is the ultimate nature of all reality?
(Relatedly, is there a God, and if so, what is God’s nature?)
(4)
What is the human being? (In particular: Are human beings free? and What is the connection between the mind and the body?)
(5)
What is the nature of causation? How does one thing cause changes in
another? (Particularly, how do the mind and body interact?)
(6) What is the good life for human beings?
(7)
What is the nature of moral claims/reasoning?
With respect to skills, this course will help you develop as a philosopher
in four key respects.
1)
First and most
importantly, you will learn to be a better philosopher. A philosopher is someone who pursues wisdom
through careful reflection. In this
course, we use modern philosophers to help our own philosophical reflection,
philosophizing with them and through philosophical critique of them.
By the end of this course, you will learn how to follow through on
philosophical insights in historical and systematic ways.
2)
Second, we will
read difficult texts and read them carefully. Reading (and the related skill of
listening) to complex arguments expressed in unfamiliar terms will prepare you
for engaging with those who hold viewpoints or forms of expression different
form your own and thus for thriving in an increasingly diverse world.
3)
Third, you will
learn both to explain the ideas of others and to articulate your own ideas
orally and in writing. Everyone is expected
to participate in class discussion in a respectful way, and one of the goals of
this course is to help all students develop confident, articulate, respectful
modes of oral communication. In
addition, everyone will write at least two papers over the course of the
semester (see details below on “writing papers in the history of
philosophy”). You will have the
opportunity to regularly submit drafts of written work for feedback.
4)
Fourth, through
group assignments and class discussions, you will learn to work effectively in
group settings and will cultivate practices of respectful, productive,
mutually-enriching philosophical interaction with your peers.
These skills will be
cultivated through several different kinds of assignments, some of which will also
provide the opportunity to learn (or apply) various technical skills, such as
designing and printing posters, producing and editing audio recordings, and so
on, that are relevant to the communication of your ideas. You have considerable flexibility about which
assignments you complete over the course of the semester. Some assignments are required of every
student, and each student must select other assignments to add up to a “full”
load of assignments for the course.
While not required, I particularly encourage students to complete
assignments that will push them to develop skills at which they might not think
of themselves as particularly excellent.
This course is an opportunity to learn and improve, not primarily an opportunity to show how good you already
are.
With the exception of the
final paper or exam and the quizzes, which count for all students, if a student
completes more than the required number of assignments, only the best 100% will
be counted towards her final grade.[1] If a student completes both the final exam
and the final paper, the better of these (or both) will be included in their
final grade. All of these assignments
are described in detail at the end of the syllabus, but here is a brief
snapshot of course requirements:
Required
of all students (80%): Careful
Reading and Reflection (0%) Participation,
Quizzes & Reading Guides (10%) Descartes
Paper (10%) Presentation
(15%) Mid-term Exam
(20%) Final Paper
or Final Exam (25%) |
Choose
enough to add up to 20% or more of your final grade: Group Projects (Hobbes, Spinoza, Locke, or/and Hume;
20% each, due dates on timeline below) Philosophical exegesis paper (10%) Analytical critique paper (10%) Final exam (25%, written or oral) |
Class Time and Rules for Discussion: This class
meets less than three hours a week, and most of the learning for the class
occurs outside of our formal class meetings, through your own careful reading
and thinking about the material, writing papers, working in groups (both
formally and informally), and meetings with me during office hours.
Lectures. My goal is to use our class periods to accomplish
goals that could not easily be accomplished outside of class. This will include some general lecturing, but
I generally do not lecture extensively, for two reasons. First, extensive empirical (psychological)
evidence and my own personal experience confirm that learning happens best
through active engagement rather than passive listening. Thus much of what would normally go into
lectures has been built into my “reading guides,” which help guide you through
the readings without telling you precisely how to think about them. Second, lectures from me are not the best way
to get expert commentary on the texts we are reading. Every figure that we read has at least one
major entry in the Stanford Encyclopedia
of Philosophy,
and most also have Cambridge Companions
available in the library. These
reference sources provide high quality commentary on the texts we are reading, and the Stanford
Encyclopedia in particular is designed to be used by undergraduates at your
level.
Quizzes: Most class
periods will begin with a short quiz on the reading for the day. The questions on these quizzes will either be
taken directly from the reading guide or will be extremely easy to answer for
anyone who has completed that reading guide.
If you completed the reading guide and did not ace the quiz, please tell
me. Occasionally, I may orally
“cold-call” on students to talk about their responses to various parts of the
reading guide. Responses that show a
failure to have read the material attentively will count against a students’
quiz grade.
Presentations. The period from 1600-1800 in Europe was the most vibrant period in the history
of philosophy, and the major philosophers we focus on in this course represent
only a small fraction of the philosophers who developed exciting and
well-developed philosophies worth taking seriously today. Thus a portion of most classes will be
devoted to a presentation on another major modern philosopher. This will give each of you a relatively easy
way to get a sense for the breadth of philosophy during this period, and it
will also give each of you an opportunity to prepare and offer a philosophical
presentation to your peers. (For more
details on these presentations, see “Course Assignments” below.)
Discussions. The main use
of our class time will be discussions amongst the entire class. These discussions provide ways to engage with
the material in sustained ways, but they also – even more importantly – provide
a context to practice the virtues of excellent participation in intellectual
group discussion. These virtues include
the following:
Preparation. You should come to class having read and thought
about the material, so that you have an informed perspective on it.
Attentive
listening. You should pay
close attention to what I, and your
peers, are saying.
Whitman has excellent faculty, but we are the excellent college that we
are because of the quality of our students.
Your classmates have insightful things to contribute to our discussion;
classmates comments are often more insightful than my own and are usually more
directly relevant to your own readings of the texts.
Boldness and
patience. Boldness and patience are both virtues in
conversation. You should participate,
even when you are not entirely sure that what you have to say is profound and
well-formulated, but you should also be patient, letting your own ideas mature
and providing opportunities for others to contribute to the conversation. Some of you will need to focus on boldness,
forcing yourselves to speak even before you are fully comfortable. (If you are one of these students, one good
practice is to prepare some comments and questions before class and to raise
these at the first opportunity. Another
good practice is to speak or raise your hand whenever there is more than 3
seconds of “dead time,” even if you don’t think what you have to say is
particularly profound.) Some will need
to focus on patience, holding back to practice attentive listening and to give
others the opportunity to contribute.
(If you are one of these, one good practice is to count to five before
speaking or raising your hand. Another
is to take the time to find textual support for your views before you
articulate them.)
Respectful
engagement with others’ views. I expect you to engage with one another’s
comments in class. Discussions should
not be public dialogues with me. This engagement will often involve answering
or refining another student’s question, taking another student’s point further,
providing additional textual support for a point that a classmate makes, and so
on. Engagement also can and often should
involve criticism of the views of others, but such criticism should always
remain respectful. Everyone in this room
(including myself) is in the process of learning to philosophize well. When we criticize one another, it should be
in the spirit of helping each other to develop as philosophers, not in an
attempt to show that one person is better than another.
Growth
mindset. Just as you engage respectfully with others,
respect those who engage with your own views.
My assumption in this course is that every comment that everyone makes
(including myself) is provisional. In class, we are trying to benefit from our conversation, not to
score points in it. And that means that
when others offer objections or criticisms of your comments in class, these are
not evidence of your inadequacy as a philosopher; they are opportunities for
you (and your interlocutor) to grow. You
should defend your view as effectively as you can, but you should also change
your view when you come to see that it is not defensible. (This point is also relevant to comments you
receive from me on your work. Your primary goal in all the work you do for this
class should be growth and development, and I will give comments with that goal
in mind.)
“Class
participation.” Your participation
can have a significant impact on your final grade. When evaluating participation, however, I am
not interested merely in the quantity of comments. A student who dominates class discussion but
fails to show the virtues listed above may have their overall grade lowered due
to poor participation. A student who
speaks occasionally but in well-informed, respectful, growing ways may have
their grade raised. (A student who never
speaks in class, however, cannot effectively demonstrate the above virtues.) If you are concerned about your
participation, either because you fear participating too much or too little,
please ask me about it at any time.
Small Group
Work. Occasionally, we will divide the class into
small groups for more focused work. This
provides those who might be timid in a large group setting an opportunity to
participate more actively, and it provides a different – and often healthy –
dynamic for discussion. All of the
virtues listed above apply to work in small groups. In addition, it is particularly important in
these groups that students remain “on task.”
Timeline of Readings and Assignments
|
Reading (Except where noted,
page numbers refer to the 2009 edition of Ariew and
Watkins, Modern Philosophy) |
Presentation
Option(s) |
Assignments |
August 29 |
Descartes,
selections from Discourse and Meditation 1 (AW 25-42) Consult the Descartes
Reading Guide as you read. |
Marie de Gournay (presentation by Patrick Frierson) |
|
Aug. 31 |
Descartes’s Meditations 1-3 & selected objections and replies 43-54, 69-72, 76-82 |
Francis Bacon Michel de Montaigne |
|
Sept 5 |
Descartes’s Meditations 2-6 & selected objections and
replies 47-68, 72-75, 86b (especially “my only remaining concern…”), 92b (especially “finally, as to the
fact”) |
Malebranche (and possibly Arnauld
and/or Gassendi) |
|
Sept. 7 |
Descartes’s Meditations 5-6 58-68 Selections from the correspondence between Descartes and Princess Elizabeth (Atherton volume, pp. 9-21). |
Galileo |
|
Sept. 12 |
Selections from the Discourse on |
Guillaume
du Vair and/or Pierre Nicole and/or the French Cartesiennes (Anne del la Vigne,
Marie Dupre, and Catherine Descartes) |
|
Sept. 14 |
Thomas Hobbes,
Objections to the Meditations (pp. 76-82) AND Leviathan
(not all this material is included in Ariew and
Watkins) |
Galileo Margaret Cavendish |
Descartes
Paper, Rough Draft Due by 11 AM, Thursday, September
15. You should email a copy of your
paper to me at frierspr@whitman.edu
and also bring a hard copy to class. Final Draft due Monday, September 19,
at 9 AM. |
Sept. 19 |
Hobbes Leviathan,
Chapters 1-2, 5-6, 13-16 (pp. 6-15, 26-40, 79-106) |
|
|
Sept. 21 |
Hobbes Leviathan,
chapters 13-18 (pp. 79-117) |
Machiavelli and/or Hugo Grotius |
|
Sept. 26 |
Spinoza, Ethics, Part V, Prop. 42 and Part 1,
entire. (Focus on propositions 10, 14,
28, and the Appendix.) (AW 195,
144-164) You should consult
this Spinoza
Reading Guide as you read. |
Pascal |
Hobbes Project due Wednesday, September 27th,
at 9 AM. |
Sept. 28 |
Spinoza, Ethics, Ethics, Pt. 2., entire (focus
on Propositions 1, 2, 7, 11-14 (including the scholium to P13), and 40-44. (AW 144-187) |
Anne Conway |
|
Oct. 3 |
Spinoza, Ethics,
From etext: Part Four, Preface, Definitions, Axiom, and
Propositions 8, 11, 14, 19, 24,
28, 36, 37, 50, 53, 54, 64, 66, 67,
68, 72, 73 (with their
Notes/Scholiums and the proofs for those in bold) From your book: Pt. 5, Preface and P21-28, 42 (AW 179-83, 188-95) |
Leibniz |
Spinoza Project Due
Wednesday, October 4, at midnight. Mid-term handed out in class on
October 3. You can find a review sheet
here
and last year’s midterm here. This midterm is closed-book,
closed-note. You may take up to 2 ½
hours to complete the exam. |
Oct. 5 (Break) |
|
|
|
Oct. 10 |
Locke’s Essay Bk I, ch
1-3, Bk II, chs 1-2, 5-12 (especially ch. 8 ¶¶9-23) Leibniz’s New Essays, selection AW 316-18, 322-42, 422-425a Consult the Locke
Reading Guide as you read. |
Leibniz (and/or possibly
Voltaire) |
Midterm due at the start of class. |
Oct. 12 |
Locke’s Essay Bk II, chs
21, 28 (chapter 23 optional but recommended if you are interested in
substance) AW 348-367 |
Berkeley |
|
Oct. 17 |
Locke’s Essay IV.1-3, 10-15, especially
IV.1-3, IV.10; IV.11¶¶8-14; IV.15¶¶1-5 AW 386-99, 405-411, 413-14, 415-17 |
Damaris Cudworth (aka Lady Masham) and/or Ralph Cudworth |
|
Oct. 19 |
Cockburn, Defense of Mr. Locke’s Essay,
selections Damaris Cudworth (Lady Masham), selections from
correspondence (both are in
Atherton, pp. 77-95, 126-146) |
Sor Juana de la Cruz, and/or Catherine Cockburn |
|
Oct. 24 |
John Locke The Second
Treatise of Civil Government, Preface and Chapter 1-6. Also review Essay, Ariew
and Watkins, pp. 397-99 |
Samuel Clarke and/or
Henry More and/or Ralph Cudworth |
|
Oct. 26 |
Locke Second Treatise, Chapters 8-19
(especially 8, 9, 18, and 19) |
Samuel Pufendorf and/or Mary Astell and/or Emilie du Chatelet |
Locke Project Due on Monday, October
30, at 9 AM. |
Oct. 31 |
Hume’s Enquiry §§ 1-7 533-564 Consult the Hume
Reading Guide as you read. |
Robert Boyle |
|
Nov. 2 |
Hume’s Enquiry §§ 6-8, 10 555-575, 577-586 Possible selections
from Reid or Rousseau Optional readings: Hume’s Enquiry §12 Hume’s Treatise I.v-vi 593-600, 517-32 |
Isaac Newton or Thomas Reid |
|
Nov. 7 |
Hume Enquiry on
Morals |
Joseph
Butler and/or
Shaftesbury and/or Hutcheson |
|
Nov 9 |
Hume Enquiry on
Morals |
Adam
Smith |
Hume
Project Due at 9 PM on Sunday, November 12th. |
Nov 14 |
Kant, Critique of Pure Reason 717-737 + this
short online handout Consult the Kant
Reading Guide. |
Thomas Reid |
|
Nov. 16 |
Kant, Critique of Pure Reason 722, 729-37, 768-779 |
Mary
Shepherd or Isaac Newton |
|
THANKSGIVING |
THANKSGIVING |
THANKSGIVING |
|
Nov. 28 |
Kant, Critique of Pure Reason 724a, 768-779, 798-800, 811-19, handout (from Critique of Practical Reason) |
Rousseau |
|
Nov. 30 |
Kant Groundwork, Preface and Part One |
Mary Wollstonecraft
and/or J.S. Mill and/or Jeremy Bentham |
|
Dec.
5 |
Kant Groundwork, Parts One and Two. |
Hegel and/or
Kierkegaard and/or Nietzsche |
|
Dec. 7 |
Last
Class Day, Review |
|
|
Dec. 11 |
FINAL
EXAM AT 9 AM |
STUDY GUIDE HERE. |
Course Assignments
Reading and Participation: All students
are expected to come to every class having read
the assigned material at least twice and to have thought
carefully about it. I do not necessarily expect you to have a complete
understanding of the material, but you should read carefully and repeatedly
until you have a good understanding of much of what is assigned, and for the
material that you do not understand, you should come to class with specific questions about what you do not
understand. If I call on you to explain a particular passage, you should not
respond “I didn’t get that passage.” Instead, you should say, “Well, thought
that Spinoza meant such-and-such, but then I couldn’t figure out how to
reconcile that understanding with what he said later, when he said
this-and-that, since this-and-that seems to conflict with such-and-such in this
particular way.” If your understanding
is still at the “I don’t get it” level, then you have more work to
do. If it’s at the “I thought that he
meant . . . but . . .,” then I have work to do.
In addition, I have provided Reading Guides for many of the readings
we will do in the course. You should
make use of these readings guides as you read and reread. You need not provide written answers to every
question, but you should think about
every question, and writing out answers is strongly recommended. I may check these guides occasionally, I will
feel free to call on any student to give their answer to any question in the
reading guide, and they will inform my decisions about what to include in
quizzes.
Participation
in class discussion is an essential part of the class,
I may alter final grades either up or down, depending upon your participation
over the course of the semester. Note
that your participation grade is based on the quality of participation, not the quantity. You should contribute thoughtful comments to class discussion in a respectful way. For some of
you, this will mean preparing oral comments before class and making a conscious
effort to speak. For others, it will
mean holding yourself back when you find yourself to be dominating
discussion. If you desire an assessment
of your participation at any point in the semester, please feel free to ask me
about it.
Deadlines: All assignments for this course should be
turned in at the date and time for which they are due. I will give a one hour grace period after
assignments are due, but after that grace period, assignments that are turned
in late will immediately be penalized by one full grade point, and the grade
will drop by an addition one point every 24 hours. (Thus an assignment that is A quality work but 61 minutes late will get a B. The same
assignment, 75 hours late, will get an F.)
I highly recommend turning in your assignments – especially group assignments
– early, and all members of a team will be held responsible for the failure of
any one member to get work done on time.
(The one exception to this policy is the final paper. Students who have a good reason for needing a
later deadline on the final paper, and who ask for that later deadline at least
one week before the paper is due, will be granted a later deadline.)
Written assignments: All written
assignments, including your papers and your group assignments, should be
submitted to me by email. To submit work
by email, you should email your work in .doc or .docx
format to frierspr@whitman.edu. You must include your first and last name as
the first terms in the filename, and the rest of the filename should make clear
what assignment you are turning in. (So, for instance, when Jane Doe turns in
her Descartes paper, she should save the paper under the filename “jane doe descartes paper.doc”.
Papers saved with the wrong filename will not be read by me. For group projects, you should save the paper
with the last name of every group participant in the filename (e.g. “doe lopez mccarty
lee spinoza project.doc”). More specific information on each assignment
is below.
Exams:
All exams will be closed book and will involve quotation identification, short
(1-3 paragraph) response questions, and at least one longer essay
question. The midterm will be a
take-home exam, for which you will be allowed two hours, though it should not
take this long. The final will be in
class at our regularly scheduled final exam time (thus you will have 2
hours). Review sheets are available on
the timeline above (where the exam appears).
Group Assignments: This course is organized around a series of
philosophers, for each of which (with the exceptions of Descartes and Kant)
there are specific projects. I have found these projects to be conducive to
learning the material, so I encourage every student to work on every assignment
throughout the semester, but you will also have the opportunity to work on some
of these assignments for credit. To get
credit for an assignment, you must work on it in a group (of 2-4 students), and
you will be graded on the project as a whole.
Each of these projects can be worth up to 20% of your final grade in the
course. Of that, approximately 15% will
be a group grade, based on the overall quality of the finished product produced
by your group.[2] The remaining 5% will be an individual grade,
based on self- and peer-assessments. For
each group assignment, the group as a whole should send me the finished
product, and each member of the group should send me an email with a short
assessment of the performance of her/himself and of each of the other members
of the group. You should provide a “score” for yourself and your peers, from 1
to 7, along with a short explanation of why you gave that score. In scoring
your teammates, you should focus not merely on specific content that group
members may have contributed, but also to the effect that the group member had
on the dynamics of the group. (A brilliant interpreter of Locke who is hostile
and uncooperative may get a 1. A student who struggles to understand very basic
arguments in Descartes but is able to ask questions well and get his teammates
to cooperate in completing the assignment well might get a 6 or 7.) I very strongly encourage you to be fair with
your assessments, both of yourself and of your teammates, and you should give
at most one score above five (and even that, only if truly warranted). Here is the meaning I intend for you to give
to the scores you assign:
1 = Unacceptable performance. This group member did not contribute to the success
of the group, and/or may even have slowed us down.
2 = Very poor.
This group member contributed something, but either the quantity or the quality
of his/her contributions were very weak. Virtually none of his/her
contributions showed up in the final result, or if they did, group members
regret not having the time to change these contributions.
3 = Below Average. This group member made real and positive contributions that improved
the final product, but not in ways as significant or pervasive as I expect of a
typical Whitman student.
4 = Average/Good. This group member did her/his duty, contributing a reasonable amount
of reasonably high quality insight, thought, hard work, and cooperative
engagement with the group. Her/his ideas made a significant and positive
contribution to the final product. (This should be the standard default score.)
5 = Very good.
This group member went above and beyond what one would expect of a typical
member of a group. S/he had insights far beyond other members of the group,
and/or raised important questions that focused on key issues, and/or explained
difficult material to other group members in particularly clear and helpful
ways, and/or helped organize or motivate the rest of the group in particularly
important ways. (You should give at most one score above 5.)
6 = Excellent.
This group member transformed the group in a way that made the final product
and the overall experience manifestly better than they would otherwise have
been. S/he was a de facto team leader, motivating and organizing us, and s/he
contributed in essential and irreplaceable ways to our performance as a team. (You should give at most one score above 5.)
7 = Extraordinary. I could not have imagined a team member as valuable as this one. S/he
should be hired as a Whitman professor, or at least as
TA for this class next year. (You should give at most one score of 7 during the
course of the semester.)
Presentations: Over the course of the semester, each student should give at least one
presentation on an important early modern philosopher we will not emphasize in
this course. If no student signs up for
a particular philosopher, we will not discuss that philosopher in this course.
If more than 2 students sign up for a particular philosopher, only the first
two who sign up will be allowed to present (as a pair) on that philosopher. You
must sign up at least 10 days before the scheduled presentation, and I
recommend signing up during the first week of class.
For
your presentation(s), you will need to read primary sources by this person and
secondary sources about them, and then pick a short selection (no more than 10
pages, preferably less than 5 pages) for your classmates to read that will give
the main points and at least one major argument of the philosopher. (These
selections must be made available to your classmates the class period prior to
your presentation. You may either email the class with a link, document, or
PDF; or bring 25 copies of the reading to hand out in class.) On the day of the
presentation, students will be expected to give a short presentation (no more
than 10 minutes) providing an overview of the philosopher on whom they are
presenting. (Powerpoint
have often been effective for these presentations, but
they should be used well.) This overview
should go substantially beyond the assigned readings; the idea is to give
fellow students a sense for the philosopher as a whole. On these days, our
class discussion in general may incorporate the readings from these
philosophers.
For each presentation,
students must prepare a paper (1500-3000 words) outlining the key aspects of
the philosopher on whom they presented.
While you may include a brief biography of the thinker, these papers
should emphasize the philosophical ideas and arguments of the philosopher. You should give at least some overview of the
philosophical views as a whole, but you may focus your discussion on one or two
ideas that you find most interesting and important. It is also appropriate to make connections
with other philosophers in the course, though this should be done in ways that
help elucidate the core ideas of the philosopher you presented on.
For presentations by groups
of more than one, each person should also submit a very brief self/peer
assessment (as for group assignments).
You can find information
about almost all of the figures you are expected to present on in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy and
on many of them in the in the Cambridge History of Seventeenth Century
Philosophy (on reserve). The Philosopher’s
Index, available through Penrose, is also a good way to find recent
scholarly articles that deal with your philosopher. You can also find information on many modern
philosophers not mentioned in the syllabus.
If you would like to present on a figure who is
not included, you will probably be able to do so if you let me know early in
the semester so that I can schedule an appropriate class time for your
presentation. Cambridge Companions are also good places to start in investigating
these philosophers (The Cambridge
Companion to Hobbes, for instance.) You are expected to make use of both
primary and secondary sources in preparing your presentation, and I strongly
encourage you to come to me for help in tracking these down. You must
make use of at least some non-electronic resources in preparing your
presentation. (Incidentally, while very helpful in some respects, Wikipedia does not constitute a legitimate
source of information for your presentations.)
Course Papers
One of the main skills that
you will learn in this class is the integration of historical-philosophical
sources into papers in which you defend your own answer to an important
philosophical problem. For both of the
required papers for the class, I will be looking for a clear, complex,
interesting, and controversial thesis that is defended with compelling
philosophical arguments in precise, elegant, and grammatically correct
prose. Both papers will also involve
interaction with historical philosophical arguments, and I am looking for a use
of such arguments that goes beyond a mere “compare and contrast” essay and
instead engages with well-articulated and textually-defended interpretations of
historical philosophers in ways that advance your own philosophical argument.
Descartes Paper (10%): This
assignment is required for all students.
At the end of the first unit of the course (on Descartes), you
will write a paper related to one of the seven philosophical problems listed
above (knowledge, diversity, reality, human being, causation, good life, or
morals). In this paper, you should
articulate a specific question related to your problem, one narrower than the
question above. (For example, instead of
“to what extent is it possible to have knowledge of anything?” you might ask,
“What is the best response to the ‘dream argument’ for philosophical
skepticism?” or “How can we have knowledge of moral claims?”) You should defend a specific thesis that
answers this question, and you should use Descartes (and, if appropriate,
Elizabeth) in the course of defending that thesis. (We will discuss in class ways for using
Descartes to defend your own thesis.)
This paper will be a first try at what you will end up doing for your
course paper at the end of the semester, so while you will not be bound to use
the same topic for the final paper, you are encouraged to choose a topic you
will want to think about for the rest of the semester. This paper should be no less than 800 and no
more than 1500 words.
Course Paper (30%): Over the course of the semester, you will write a
single, complex paper, answering a question related to one of the seven
philosophical problems listed above (knowledge, diversity, reality, human
being, causation, good life, morals). By the end of the semester, you will
write a paper of no less than 1800 and no more than 2500 words that engages
with at least three of the philosophers we study over the course of the
semester and defends a clear, complex, interesting, and controversial thesis
that answers a question related to (but more specific than) the question listed
above.[3] While
your final paper is not due until the
last day of class, you should work on it throughout the semester. Over the
course of the semester, you should update your final paper, refining your
topic, question, and thesis; and incorporating arguments from philosophers as
we read them. I strongly encourage you
to submit new paper drafts after each major philosopher, incorporating material
from that philosopher into your final paper.
Throughout the course of the semester, in addition to adding
perspectives of new philosophers, you should refine the question you aim to
answer and gradually form your own ideas about how best to answer that
question, drawing from your interactions with the philosophers we are studying.
Before submitting the final draft, you will also need to decide which figures
are the most important to include in the final draft, and you will have to cut
material that is less relevant in order to ensure that you do justice to your
topic, defend your thesis adequately, and include sufficient treatments of the
three philosophers on whom you focus. The final draft of the paper will be due
on the last day of class.
Philosophical exegesis paper (10%) Your final paper and paper on Descartes must
offer your own answer to a
philosophical problem, drawing from major historical figures. But historians of philosophy often write
papers that purport to elucidate the ideas of a philosopher without necessarily
defending those ideas as their own. Papers in philosophical exegesis generally
start with a puzzle of interpretation.
For example, Anne Conway says that there is only one created
“substance,” but also that there are infinitely many created things; so what
precisely does she mean by “substance”?
Or, for another example, Berkeley does not explicitly talk about the
nature of human freedom; given what he does say, what is his likely view on
this matter? The paper then proceeds to
answer these questions, considering various possible interpretations and
defending one’s own on the basis of specific textual support, plausibility in
the light of other claims the philosopher has made, and general philosophical
plausibility. Any student can write a
philosophical exegesis paper on any of the philosophers we read in this
course. Such papers are due at the same
time as the group project for that philosopher, and they should be 1500-2500
words in length.
Analytical critique paper (10%). Where the
philosophical exegesis paper is more
historical than the final paper, the analytical critique paper is less historical. For this paper, you should take an idea or
argument from one of the philosophers we have read and engage with that
argument in your own terms. “Critique”
here need not mean criticism of the argument or position; though it often will
involve criticism, one might also extend a point made by a philosopher or show
that an argument made in one context applies equally well in another. The distinguishing feature of this paper is
that the majority of the paper will be philosophical argument rather than interpretation. As with all papers, but particularly for
these, it is important that the thesis be clearly articulated and that you be
able to see how the thesis is controversial
and even prima facie implausible. Thus, arguing that Descartes was wrong to
think that an the existence of an evil demon would
make our beliefs unreliable could be a worthwhile thesis. Arguing that he was
wrong to think that the pineal gland is the physical seat of the soul would not
be. These papers are due at the same
time as the group project for that philosopher, and they should be 1500-2500
words in length.
Group Assignment #1: Descartes vs.
Hobbes
This assignment is designed to be
done in pairs, and I strongly recommend it for all students. It will help a lot with your final
paper. One purpose of this assignment is to revisit your
Descartes paper, looking at the same issue but now from the standpoint of
Hobbes. Another purpose is to teach you
how to work with others to improve each others’
writing and to craft philosophical positions together. The project has several steps.
(1)
Revise your
Descartes paper, in the light of my comments and your further reflections. Make it the strongest Descartes paper it can
be.
(2)
Exchange papers
with your partner. Each of you should,
independently, craft a Hobbist response to the
philosophical thesis advanced in the Descartes paper. This response should be 1000-1500 words and
should advance a clear thesis, something like “While Mary successfully argues
against Descartes’s claim that the mind and body are distinct substances, she
fails to offer a plausible alternative account of the mind; seeing mind as a
faculty implanted by God would significantly improve her argument” or “Tony’s
claim that Descartes develops a plausible approach to ethics fails to take into
account the role of immortality of the soul.
Once we take an appropriate skepticism towards that immortality, we see
that ethics is essentially political.”
(3)
Exchange these
responses and then meet with your partner to discuss them. Revise and improve your Hobbist
response to your partner’s Descartes paper.
Repeat step (3) until each of you has a really good paper.
(4)
Then, together, draft a short paper 800-1000
words that defends a philosophical thesis, drawing on Hobbes, Descartes, and
each of your short papers.
You will turn in your revised
Descartes papers, your first and final drafts of your Hobbes responses, and
your short philosophical paper. The
group grade, which will be shared by both students, will be based on the final
drafts of the Hobbes responses and on the joint philosophical paper.
Group Assignment #2: Spinoza Worksheet
For each proposition below, work
through Spinoza’s whole proof. I recommend reading through the assigned
reading in the order Spinoza presents it, and then working backwards through
each key proposition’s proof, tracing back to the axioms and definitions on
which it ultimately depends. When you finally turn in the worksheet, you
should have clearly written answers to each question. (Answers to part
(a) can take the form of a simple “yes” or “no.” All other questions
should be answered with at least one clear and concise paragraph.)
1. Prop 11: God . . . necessarily exists.
a) Does
Spinoza successfully prove proposition 11?
b) If not, what
specific inferences are invalid, what specific axioms are false, and/or what
specific definitions are illegitimate? (In answering this question, be
prepared to explain in precisely what sense the inferences are invalid, the
axioms are false, or the definitions are illegitimate; and also be sure that
you have identified the precise role that such inferences, axioms, or
definitions play in Spinoza’s argument.)
c) Without considering Spinoza’s subsequent
argument about the nature of God, what significance would P 11 have for
Spinoza’s contemporaries (e.g. Descartes)?
d) Without considering Spinoza’s subsequent
argument about the nature of God, what significance would believing it have
for us?
2. Prop. 14: There can be . . . no other
substance but God.
a)
Explain P 14 without using any of Spinoza’s technical vocabulary, in a way that
would make sense and be interesting to a friend who had never read any
philosophy.
b) Given
Prop 11, does Spinoza successfully prove proposition 14?
c) If not, what specific
inferences are invalid, what specific axioms are false, and/or what specific
definitions are illegitimate? (In answering this question, be prepared to
explain in precisely what sense the inferences are invalid, the axioms are
false, or the definitions are illegitimate.) In particular, are there
any invalid inferences between P11 and P14 (or any new
axioms or definitions of which Spinoza makes use that are problematic)?
That is, is Spinoza correct that if God necessarily
exists, then there can be no substance but God?
d) What
significance would believing P 14 have for Spinoza’s contemporaries (e.g.
Descartes)?
e) What
significance would believing it have for us?
3. Prop. 28: Every individual thing . . ..
a)
Explain P 14 without using any of
Spinoza’s technical vocabulary, in a way that would make sense and be
interesting to a friend who had never read any philosophy.
b)
Given Props 11 and 14, does
Spinoza successfully prove proposition 28?
c)
If not, what specific inferences
are invalid, what specific axioms are false, and/or what specific definitions
are illegitimate? (In answering this question, be prepared to explain in
precisely what sense the inferences are invalid, the axioms are false, or the
definitions are illegitimate.)
d)
What significance would believing
P 28 have for Spinoza’s contemporaries (e.g. Descartes)?
e)
What significance would believing
it have for us?
4. Book II, Prop. 7: The order and connection of
ideas is the same as the order and connection of things.
a) What
is the significance of P 7 within Spinoza’s Ethics? (For example, what significance does it play
in understanding the definitions to part I)
b) What
significance would believing P 7 have for Spinoza’s contemporaries (e.g.
Descartes)?
c) What
significance would believing it have for us?
5. Book V, Prop 25.
For analyzing this Proposition, you should use the hypertext edition of
Spinoza’s Ethics, available at http://www.mtsu.edu/~rbombard/RB/Spinoza/ethica-front.html.
a) What
do you think would be the most problematic aspects of Spinoza’s proof of
proposition 25?
b) What
significance would believing it have for us? (Here take into account,
too, Book V, P42.)
6. Is Spinoza a better Cartesian than
Descartes? Keep your response to less
than 1000 words.
Group
Assignment #3: Lockean Poetics
Analyze
a poem in terms of Locke's Essay (and, insofar as it’s relevant, his Second
Treatise). While you may
present your results in the form of a paper, I encourage you to do a poster or
any other format for which you get prior approval from me (e.g. a short play).[4] YOU MAY ANALYZE ANY POEM THAT YOU
CHOOSE. (For a complete and
searchable e-text of Locke’s Essay, click HERE.
And HERE is a great site for finding poems.)
The analysis should explain
what sorts of ideas are referred to by some representative words in the poem.
(Aim to find at least one example each of simple ideas of sensation, simple
ideas of reflection, complex ideas of sensation and
complex ideas of reflection. If possible, you also should give examples of
primary and secondary qualities in the poem.) You should analyze the literal
meaning of the poem, discussing whether it provides "knowledge" in Lockean terms, or probable opinion, or both or neither. But
you should also discuss what you take the main point of the poem to be, what
the poem teaches, what it does to the reader, and so on. As a whole,
does the poem provide "knowledge" in Lockean
terms? If so, specifically how? If not, is this a
problem for the poem (or for Locke's theory of knowledge)?
Group Assignment #4: "Cross-Disciplinary Conversations with Hume"
(This assignment will be done in pairs.)
For this assignment, you will need to help other people explain the most
important aspects of Hume's thought, the relevance of his ideas to their chosen
discipline (major), and their opinions about his philosophy. First, you'll need
to find two friends or acquaintances who have never taken a philosophy class
and who have different majors from each other. Then, you'll need some sort of
recording device (a tape recorder, a microphone-computer set up, or something
similar). Finally, you'll need a comfortable place for a chat, and the
requisite refreshments so that you and your guest are comfortable. (Please
avoid intoxicants while you complete the assignment.) Once you are set up, the
two of you simply need to explain to your guests the basics of Hume's
philosophy, answer questions, clarify Hume’s views, find out what your guests
find most interesting about it . . . in other words, you need to have a
conversation. During this, you should take the stance of people defending Hume's
view. (Aim to be Hume-channelers.) In addition, you should specifically address
– and try to figure out with your interlocutors – the relevance of Hume to
their majors. (This is likely to work
best if you focus on one or two key examples from within their discipline, such
as a particular scientific or historical claim, or a particular approach to
art, or even a particular painting.)
Your conversation should last at least an hour, and you should record
the whole conversation. However, what
you will actually turn in is three recordings of no more than 7 minutes each
(and no more than 12 minutes total). The first recording should include what
you think is the most interesting and important 5-7 minutes of your
conversation. (This can be made up of
distinct, shorter sections of conversation, or it can be a single section.) The
second recording should be the one in which your guests most clearly explains
Hume's thought, apply that thought to their own disciplines, and give their
opinions about it. For this second
recording, you will be evaluated on the quality of your guests’ explanation. If you
are doing most of the talking, that is a sign that you have not sufficiently
explained Hume’s views to them. In
the final recording (which you can make at a later time), you should explain
what was hardest to explain about Hume, and/or any challenges that you
encountered in the course of your conversation. (At the start of the conversation,
and at the start of the recording that you turn in, you should have each
participant in the conversation state their full name, year, and major.)
For help setting up and/or editing these
tapes, you may contact Instructional Multimedia Services (see http://www.whitman.edu/content/wcts/ims/).
The recordings should all be converted into .mp3 or .wma
or some other easily readable digital form, and emailed to me.
[1] There is one other exception to this policy. Students who choose to do group assignments
and get very low peer reviews on those group assignments will have those
assignments count towards their final grade, even if they do better on other
assignments.
[2] In special circumstances, I reserve the right to weigh the
individual portion of the grade more heavily.
This will be particularly relevant in cases where a particular student
makes an extraordinarily good or extraordinarily bad contribution to their
group.
[3] For example, you may start with “What is the human being?” and
end up with a paper that answers the question “Is freedom necessary for moral
responsibility?” by using Spinoza, Hume, and Kant to argue something like,
“While Kant thinks that he can preserve human freedom as a necessary condition
of the possibility of morality, his metaphysics in fact offers decisive reasons
to reject freedom. Fortunately, as Spinoza and Hume show in very different
ways, a robust conception of moral responsibility is consistent with this
rejection of freedom.”
[4] If you do a poster, play, or other non-electronic form of presentation, you should either turn the item in to my office or arrange with me for a means of performing it/turning it in.